Skip to main content

Directions in Space, Nonconceptual Form and the Foundations of Transcendental Idealism

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Kantian Nonconceptualism

Abstract

The central aim of this chapter is to demonstrate an essential connection between Kant’s nonconceptualism and his transcendental idealism by tracing this line of thinking in Kant’s work directly back to his pre-Critical essay of 1768, Concerning the Ground of the Ultimate Differentiation of Directions in Space aka “Directions in Space”. What I shall argue is that Kant’s nonconceptualism about the human mind goes all the way down into his metaphysics; that the apparent world fundamentally conforms to human sensibility even if it does not fundamentally conform to the human understanding; and that the basic source of all this is Kant’s (pre-Critical but later also Critical) theory of space and how we represent it.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 69.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 89.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 119.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Hanna (2015), esp. Chaps. 3 and 68.

  2. 2.

    See e.g. McDowell (1994) and Sellars (1963, 1968).

  3. 3.

    See e.g. Evans (1982). In the contemporary debate about conceptualism vs nonconceptualism, it is now standard to draw a distinction between state (or possession-theoretic) nonconceptualism and content nonconceptualism. State nonconceptualism says that there are mental states such that the subject of those states fails to possess concepts for the specification of those states. Content nonconceptualism, by contrast, says that some mental states have content that is of a different kind from that of conceptual content. In turn, essentialist content nonconceptualism says that the content of such states is of a categorically or essentially different kind from that of conceptual content. For a general survey of nonconceptualism, see Bermúdez and Cahen (2015). For the distinction between state and content nonconceptualism, see Heck (2009). And for the distinction between non-essentialist and essentialist content nonconceptualism, see Hanna (2008, 2011, 2015, Chap. 2).

  4. 4.

    The inherent connections between intellectualism and conceptualism, on the one hand, and between non-intellectualism and nonconceptualism, on the other, are developed in detail in Hanna (2015), esp. Chaps. 23, and Hanna (MS), Chap. 5.

  5. 5.

    See e.g. Hanna (2005) and McDowell (1994).

  6. 6.

    See e.g. Bauer (2012), Bowman (2011), Ginsborg (2006a, 2008), Golob (2014), Griffith (2012), Grüne (2009), Land (2011), McDowell (2009, 2013), Pippin (2013), Wenzel (2005), and Williams (2012).

  7. 7.

    See e.g. Hanna (2008, 2011), Hanna and Chadha (2011), Laiho (2012), and Tolley (2013). Weaker versions of Kantian nonconceptualism are defended by e.g. Allais (2009), McLear (2015), Onof and Schulting (2015), and Rohs (2001).

  8. 8.

    See e.g. McLear (2014b).

  9. 9.

    I have substituted “representation” (Vorstellung) here and further below for Kant’s “concept” (Begriff). My rationale is this. In Hanna (2006), Chap. 5, while working out a rationally charitable step-by-step argument-reconstruction of the Transcendental Aesthetic (TAe), I argued for Kant’s shifting from a general, loose sense of “concept” in the pre-Critical and proto-Critical writings, where it basically means the same as “representation”, to a narrower, technical sense of “concept”, which means an essentially general, descriptive or “attributive” representation, in TAe and the rest of the First Critique and other Critical and post-Critical writings (including the Jäsche Logic), where it sharply contrasts with his use of “intuition”, which means an essentially singular or “directly referential” representation. This sharp contrast between the meanings of “concept” and “intuition” begins to emerge in the “Inaugural Dissertation”, but unfortunately they are not made fully terminologically explicit there. Moreover, and to make things even worse for interpreters, in TAe Kant still does not fully terminologically update the material he took from the “Inaugural Dissertation”, and occasionally uses “concept” of space (or time) when he really means “representation of space (or time)” or “pure intuition of space (or time)”. This causes not only significant interpretive confusion, it also gives the false appearance of occasionally making Kant seem blatantly self-contradictory—e.g. when he says explicitly that the “concept” of space (or time) is not a concept but instead a pure intuition, etc. Assuming all this is true, and again applying rational charity in philosophical interpretation, we can avoid equal confusion in the retrospective, proto-Critical direction only by substituting “representation” for “concept” in Directions in Space, when Kant would, with philosophical hindsight, clearly intend to be talking either neutrally about representations that are either “concepts” or “intuitions” in the later, narrower, technical senses of those terms, or else specifically about “intuitions” in the later, narrower, technical sense.

  10. 10.

    See e.g. McLear (2011).

  11. 11.

    For more fully spelled out versions of this argument, see Hanna (2008, 2011).

  12. 12.

    See note 9 above, and also Hanna (2001), Chaps. 4 and 5.

  13. 13.

    There are also several more exciting but also less obvious examples, all of which have to do with the real possibility of human freedom. See Hanna (2011, 2016).

  14. 14.

    See also Schulting (2015b).

Bibliography

  • Allais, Lucy. 2009. Kant, Non-Conceptual Content and the Representation of Space. Journal of the History of Philosophy 47(3): 383–413.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bauer, N 2012. A Peculiar Intuition: Kant’s Conceptualist Account of Perception. Inquiry 55(3): 215–237.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bermúdez, J., and A. Cahen. 2015. Nonconceptual Mental Content. In Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed. E. Zalta, http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2015/entries/content-nonconceptual/ .

  • Bowman, B. 2011. A Conceptualist Reply to Hanna’s Kantian Non-Conceptualism. International Journal of Philosophical Studies 19(3): 417–446.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Evans, G. 1982. The Varieties of Reference. In ed. J. McDowell (Oxford: Clarendon Press).

    Google Scholar 

  • Ginsborg, H 2006a. Empirical Concepts and the Content of Experience. European Journal of Philosophy 14(3): 349–372.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ——— 2008. Was Kant a Nonconceptualist? Philosophical Studies 137(1): 65–77 [also published in D. Heidemann (2013), pp. 208–18.].

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Golob, S. 2014. Kant on Intentionality, Magnitude, and the Unity of Perception. European Journal of Philosophy 22(4): 505–528.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Griffith, A. 2012. Perception and the Categories: A Conceptualist Reading of Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason. European Journal of Philosophy 20(2): 193–222.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grüne, S 2009. Blinde Anschauung. Die Rolle von Begriffen in Kants Theorie sinnlicher Synthesis. Frankfurt a/M: Klostermann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hanna, R. 2001. Kant and the Foundations of Analytic Philosophy. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hanna, R 2005. Kant and Nonconceptual Content. European Journal of Philosophy 13(2): 247–290.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ——— 2006. Kant, Science, and Human Nature. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • ——— 2008. Kantian Non-Conceptualism. Philosophical Studies 137(1): 41–64.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ——— 2015. Cognition, Content, and the A Priori. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • ——— 2016a. Blind Intuitions, Essentially Rogue Objects, and Categorial Anarchy.

    Google Scholar 

  • ——— 2016b. Sensibility First: From Kantian Non-Conceptualism to Kantian Non-Intellectualism.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hanna, R., and M. Chadha. 2011. Non-Conceptualism and the Problem of Perceptual Self-Knowledge. European Journal of Philosophy 19(2): 184–223.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heck, R 2009. Are There Different Kinds of Content? In Contemporary Debates in Philosophy of Mind, eds. B. McLaughlin and J. Cohen, 117–138. Malden, MA: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laiho, H. 2012. Perception in Kant’s Model of Experience. Ph.D. dissertation: University of Turku.

    Google Scholar 

  • Land, T. 2011. Kantian Conceptualism. In Rethinking Epistemology, eds. G. Abel et al., 197–239. Berlin: de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, J 1994. Mind and World. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ——— 2009. Having the World in View: Essays on Kant, Hegel, and Sellars. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ——— 2013. The Myth of the Mind as Detached. In Mind, Reason and Being-in-the-World. The McDowell-Dreyfus Debate, ed. J. Schear, 41–58. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • McLear, C. 2011. Kant on Animal Consciousness. Philosophers’ Imprint 11(15): 1–16.

    Google Scholar 

  • McLear, C 2015. Two Kinds of Unity in the Critique of Pure Reason. Journal of the History of Philosophy 53(1): 79–110.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Onof, C., and D. Schulting. 2015. Space as Form of Intuition and as Formal Intuition: On the Note to B160 in Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason. Philosophical Review 124(1): 1–58.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pippin, R 2013. What is “Conceptual Activity”? In Mind, Reason and Being-in-the-World. The McDowell-Dreyfus Debate, ed. J. Schear, 91–109. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rohs, P. 2001. Bezieht sich nach Kant die Anschauung unmittelbar auf Gegenstände? In Akten des 9. Internationalen Kant-Kongresses. Bd. II, eds. R.-P. Horstmann et al., 214–228. Berlin and New York: de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schulting, D 2015b. Probleme des “kantianischen” Nonkonzeptualismus im Hinblick auf die B-Deduktion. Kant-Studien 106(4): 561–580.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sellars, W. 1963. Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind. In Science, Perception, and Reality, ed. W. Sellars, 127–196. New York: Humanities Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sellars, W 1968. Science and Metaphysics: Variations on Kantian Themes. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tolley, C. 2013. The Non-Conceptuality of the Content of Intuitions: A New Approach. Kantian Review 18(1): 107–136.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wenzel, C. 2005. Spielen nach Kant die Kategorien schon bei der Wahrnehmung eine Rolle? Peter Rohs und John McDowell. Kant-Studien 96(4): 407–426.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williams, J. 2012. How Conceptually-Guided are Kantian Intuitions? History of Philosophy Quarterly 29(1): 57–78.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Robert Hanna .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Copyright information

© 2016 The Author(s)

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Hanna, R. (2016). Directions in Space, Nonconceptual Form and the Foundations of Transcendental Idealism. In: Schulting, D. (eds) Kantian Nonconceptualism. Palgrave Macmillan, London. https://doi.org/10.1057/978-1-137-53517-7_5

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics