Skip to main content

Narrating Lessons and Collective Learning Processes

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Lessons from the Past?

Part of the book series: Palgrave Macmillan Memory Studies ((PMMS))

  • 433 Accesses

Abstract

Forchtner moves from describing claims to know the lessons from the past towards considering their evaluation and normative aspects. Instead of discussing how claims to know position subjects, this chapter thus turns to the notion of learning from the past. What would a notion of learning in line with narrative theory look like? How could it be linked to the four rhetorics? And what are the theoretical foundations on which it could be justified? He draws on the Habermasian notion of intersubjectivity and the concept of collective learning processes, i.e. processes through which intersubjective relations become more open and egalitarian. These approaches are then revised by including narrative theory, in particular the aforementioned modes of emplotment which he understands as social mechanisms rather enabling or blocking collective learning processes.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    This sharp separation is not entirely convincing as Margalit (2002, p. 182) himself talks about the moral witness as ‘systematically ambiguous between ethics and morality’.

  2. 2.

    Habermas (1998, 1989) has frequently intervened in debates over the past. These interventions, however, are political writings and rather implicitly draw on his reconstruction of immanent potentials in human interaction; and I will thus not focus on them.

  3. 3.

    There is a basic division between non-social action oriented towards success (actor-object) and social action (actor-actor). Social action is then further divided into either strategic action or action oriented towards understanding, i.e. communicative action. The latter has been further differentiated (Habermas, 2003).

  4. 4.

    Another criticism concerns the fact that arguments cannot last forever—a point to which Habermas (1990b, p. 92) responds by arguing for institutional measures which ‘sufficiently neutralise empirical limitations and avoidable internal and external interference so that the idealised conditions pragmatically presupposed by participants in argumentation can at least be adequately approximated’.

  5. 5.

    Consider also Foucault’s comment concerning polemics in Sect. 3.2.

  6. 6.

    In this context, I avoid discussing Glynos’ subsequent turn to Lacan’s ethics of the drive.

  7. 7.

    Although I cannot develop this here, let me include a further quote from Derrida (1996, p. 84) on the messianic structure belonging to all language use (and bearing a certain resemblance to the above outlined reconstruction): ‘There is no language without the performative dimension of the promise, the minute I open my mouth I am in the promise. Even if I say that “I don’t believe in truth” or whatever, the minute I open my mouth there is a “believe me” at work. Even when I lie, and perhaps especially when I lie, there is a “believe me” in play. And this “I promise you that I am speaking the truth” is a messianic apriori, a promise which, even if it is not kept, even if one knows that it cannot be kept, takes place and qua promise is messianic’.

References

  • Anker, E. R. (2014). Orgies of feeling. Melodrama and the politics of freedom. Durham: Duke University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Assmann, A., & Shortt, L. (2012). Memory and political change: Introduction. In L. Shortt & A. Assmann (Eds.), Memory and political change (pp. 1–14). Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Austin, J. L. (1975). How to do things with words. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bächtiger, A., Niemeyer, S., Neblo, M., Steenbergen, M. R., & Steiner, J. (2010). Disentangling diversity in deliberative democracy: Competing theories, their blind spots and complementarities. Journal of Political Philosophy, 18(1), 32–63.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bluestein, J. (2008). The moral demands of memory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Booth, J. W. (2006). Communities of memory. On witness, identity, and justice. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boswell, J. (2013). Why and how narrative matters in deliberative systems. Political Studies, 61, 620–636.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bourdieu, P. (2000). Pascalian meditations. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Critchley, S. (2014). The ethics of deconstruction: Derrida and Levinas. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Derrida, J. (1993). Aporias. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Derrida, J. (1996). Remarks on deconstruction and pragmatism. In C. Mouffe (Ed.), Deconstruction and pragmatism (pp. 79–90). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Derrida, J. (2001). On cosmopolitanism and forgiveness. London: Taylor & Francis.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eder, K. (1985). Geschichte als Lernprozeß? Zur Pathogenese politischer Modernität in Deutschland. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eder, K. (1988). Die Vergesellschaftung der Natur. Studien zur sozialen Evolution der praktischen Vernunft. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eder, K. (1999). Societies learn and yet the world is hard to change. European Journal of Social Theory, 2, 195–215.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eder, K. (2009). Rational choice, communicative action, and the narrative structure of social life. In S. Ó. Tuama (Ed.), Critical turns in critical theory. New directions in social and political thought (pp. 63–80). London: I.B. Tauris.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ellis, D. (2014). Narrative as deliberative argument. Dynamics of Asymmetric Conflict: Pathways Toward Terrorism and Genocide, 7(1), 95–108.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Engelken-Jorge, M. (2016). Narrative deliberation? On storytelling as a necessary component of public deliberation. Política Y Sociedad, 53(1), 79–99.

    Google Scholar 

  • Erll, A. (2011). Travelling memory. Parallax, 17(4), 4–18.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Forchtner, B., & Eder, K. (forthcoming). Europa erzählen: Strukturen Europäischer Identität. In H.-W. Platzer & G. Hentges (Eds.), Europäische Identität in der Krise? Wiesbaden: VS.

    Google Scholar 

  • Forchtner, B., & Schneickert, C. (2016). Collective learning in social fields: Bourdieu, Habermas and critical discourse studies. Discourse & Society, 27(3), 293–307.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Glynos, J. (2000). Thinking the ethics of the political in the context of a postfoundational world: From an ethics of desire to an ethics of the drive. Theory & Event, 4(4). https://muse.jhu.edu/article/32603. Accessed 10 Sep 2016.

  • Habermas, J. (1977). A review of Gadamer’s truth and method. In F. R. Dallmayr & T. A. McCarthy (Eds.), Understanding and social inquiry (pp. 335–361). Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, J. (1979a). What is universal pragmatics. In Communication and the evolution of society (pp. 1–68). London: Heinemann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, J. (1979b). Towards a reconstruction of historical materialism. In Communication and the evolution of society (pp. 130–177). London: Heinemann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, J. (1984). The theory of communicative action. Volume I. Reason and the rationalization of society. Cambridge: Polity.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, J. (1987). The theory of communicative action. Volume II. Lifeworld and system. Cambridge: Polity.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, J. (1989). The new conservatism. Cambridge: Polity.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, J. (1990a). The philosophical discourse of modernity. Twelve lectures. Cambridge: Polity.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, J. (1990b). Discourse ethics: Notes on a program of philosophical justification. In Moral consciousness and communicative action (pp. 43–115). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, J. (1993). Remarks on discourse ethics. In Justification and application. Remarks on discourse ethics (pp. 19–111). Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, J. (1996). Further reflections on the public sphere. In C. Calhoun (Ed.), Habermas and the public sphere (pp. 421–461). Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, J. (1997). Between facts and norms: Contributions to a discourse theory of law and democracy. Cambridge: Polity.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, J. (1998). A Berlin Republic: Writings on Germany. Cambridge: University of Nebraska Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, J. (2001). Reflections on communicative pathology. In On the pragmatics of social interaction: Preliminary studies in the theory of communicative action (pp. 131–170). Cambridge: Polity.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, J. (2003). Some further clarifications on the concept of communicative rationality. In On the pragmatics of communication (pp. 307–342). Cambridge: Polity.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, J. (2005). Hermeneutic and analytical philosophy: Two complementary versions of the linguistic turn. In Truth and Justification (pp. 51–81). Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, J. (2008). Communicative action and the detranscendentalized “use of reason”. In Between naturalism and religion: Philosophical essays (pp. 24–76). Cambridge: Polity.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jacobs, R. N., & Smith, P. (1997). Romance, irony, and solidarity. Sociological Theory, 15(1), 60–80.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jürgen, H. (1974). Introduction: Some difficulties in the attempt to link theory and praxis. In Theory and practice (pp. 1–40). London: Heinemann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Karner, C., & Mertens, B. (2013). Introduction: Memories and analogies of world war II. In C. Karner & B. Mertens (Eds.), The use and abuse of memory. Interpreting world war II in contemporary European politics (pp. 1–21). New Brunswick: Transaction.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levy, D., & Sznaider, N. (2010). Human rights and memory. Pennsylvania: The rPennsylvania State University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Margalit, A. (2002). The ethics of memory. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Miller, M. (1986). Kollektive Lernprozesse. Studien zur Grundlegung einer soziologischen Lerntheorie. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Miller, M. (2006). Dissens. Zur Theorie diskursiven und systemischen Lernens. Bielefeld: transcript.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Moses, D. (2005). Hayden white, traumatic nationalism, and the public role of history. History and Theory, 44: 111–332.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moses, D., & Rothberg, M. (2014). A dialogue on the ethics and politics of transcultural memory. In L. Bond & J. Rapson (Eds.), The transcultural turn interrogating memory between and beyond borders (pp. 29–38). Berlin: De Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Müller, J.-W. (2002). Introduction: The power of memory, the memory of power and the power over memory. In J.-W. Müller (Ed.), Memory and power in post-war Europe (pp. 1–35). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Munslow, A. (2006). Deconstructing history. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reading, A. (2011). Identity, memory and cosmopolitanism: The otherness of the past and a right to memory? European Journal of Cultural Studies, 14(4), 379–394.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ricoeur, P. (2004). Memory, history, forgetting. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rothberg, M. (2009). Multidirectional memory: Remembering the Holocaust in the age of decolonization. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strydom, P. (1992). The ontogenetic fallacy: The immanent critique of Habermas’s developmental logical theory of evolution. Theory, Culture & Society, 9: 65–93.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, J. (2002). Taking responsibility for the past: The future of European Governance: Reparation and historical injustice. Cambridge: Polity.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wagner-Pacifici, R. (2012). Aldo Moro and the tragic afterlife of a melodrama. In R. Glynn & G. Lombardi (Eds.), Remembering Aldo Moro. The cultural legacy of the 1978 kidnapping and murder (pp. 30–37). Oxford: Legenda.

    Google Scholar 

  • White, H. (1966). The burden of history. History and Theory, 5(2), 111–134.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • White, H. (2014). The practical past. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams, L. (1998). Melodrama revised. In N. Browne (Ed.), Refiguring American film genres. History and theory. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Copyright information

© 2016 The Author(s)

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Forchtner, B. (2016). Narrating Lessons and Collective Learning Processes. In: Lessons from the Past?. Palgrave Macmillan Memory Studies. Palgrave Macmillan, London. https://doi.org/10.1057/978-1-137-48322-5_7

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics