Skip to main content

When Actions Feel Alien—an Explanatory Model

  • Conference paper
  • First Online:
Book cover Communicative Action

Abstract

It is not necessarily the case that we ever have experiences of self, but human beings do regularly report instances for which self is experienced as absent. That is, there are times when body parts, mental states, or actions are felt to be alien. Here, I sketch an explanatory framework for explaining these alienation experiences, a framework that also attempts to explain the “mental glue” whereby self is bound to body, mind, or action. The framework is a multidimensional model that integrates personal and sub-personal components, psychological and neural processes. I then proceed to show how this model can be applied to explain the action-related passivity experiences of persons suffering from schizophrenia. I argue that a distinctive phenomenological mark of these experiences is that they are vividly felt, unlike ordinary actions (those taken to belong to self), and I seek to explain these heightened sensory experiences from within the proposed framework. I also propose hypotheses concerning such phenomena as thought insertion and anarchic hand syndrome that are motivated by this framework. Finally, I argue that the proposed model and view of self-experiences is consistent with several aspects of and theories of consciousness, especially theories which indicate that consciousness is more likely to be engaged when we are dealing with novelty or error—e.g., when self seems to have gone missing. I conclude by recommending that if we wish to learn about self, we would be well advised to attend closely to those times when it seems absent.

“The self is an absence…” (Sorensen 2007, p. 450)

“…we can feel the absence of the self…but not the presence of the self.” (Prinz 2012a, p. 148)

An erratum to this chapter can be found at http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/978-981-4585-84-2_9

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    There is something potentially misleading about talk of a relationship between self and body parts, mental states, or actions. Talk of belonging or mental glue in such contexts suggests a two-place relation, which is not the case, at least not if one of the relata is taken to be an experience of self (cf. Prinz 2012b, p. 231). Although for expository purposes I do write in such a way that a relationship of this type might seem to be implied, as I explain below, “self” here is taken to be a distinctive type of neural activity, not an experience in and of itself. What Baars et al. (2003) and Baars (2007) metaphorically refer to as the brain’s “observing self” is a useful way to think of this relationship.

  2. 2.

    Throughout this manuscript I use “introspection” in what Shoemaker (1994, p. 258) dubs the “humdrum” sense, referring to information we have access to that is expressed in such remarks as “it itches,” “I’m thirsty,” and so forth.

  3. 3.

    The thalamus projects a large number of axons to all parts of the cortex; the cortex projects an even greater number of axons to the thalamus (Jones 2007).

  4. 4.

    Italics not contained in the original.

  5. 5.

    These experiments attempt to capture, under controlled conditions, certain aspects of what persons experience when they play with an Ouija board.

  6. 6.

    Somewhat similar reactions to pain have been reported for those who have undergone surgical ablation of pathways linking the thalamus with parts of the frontal lobes (Klein 2013a, pp. 91–93).

  7. 7.

    Instances of mental states failing to cluster in tacitly expected ways are plentiful. To cite just one other example, those who suffer from motion blindness have otherwise normal visual experiences of the external world, but their ability to perceive motion is greatly impaired (e.g., Zihl et al. 1983). Typically visual perceptions of color and shape cluster with motion. But in these rare cases, clustering fails.

  8. 8.

    CMS regions include the perigenual anterior cingulate cortex, the dorsomedial prefrontal cortex, and the posterior cingulated cortex. The CMS overlaps with Feinberg’s (2009, pp. 152–155) “integrative self-system” and with the default-mode network (Raichle 2010), which has also been implicated in self-referential processing.

  9. 9.

    I will not develop my reasons in detail, but I submit that part of the confusion in this vicinity is due to a failure to distinguish clearly and consistently between “qualitative” psychological states, like perceptions and sensations, and “non-qualitative” states, like beliefs or desires (cf. Rosenthal 2005, pp. 218–219, 303–305). Bayne et al., when referring to ordinary action, seem to be writing about non-qualitative states. My position is that in ordinary action the qualitative states though are silent. That is, ordinarily, when we act, our actions are not accompanied by distinctive perceptions or sensations. As to whether ordinary actions are accompanied by distinctive non-qualitative states, that is a separate issue.

  10. 10.

    The visual experience that objects in the world are moving, when they are actually stationary, can also be caused by gently pressing the eyeball or by paralyzing the eye with curare (Stephens and Graham 2000, p. 136).

  11. 11.

    Binding comprises both a predictive and a retrospective mechanism; schizophrenia is associated with an impairment to the former (Voss et al. 2010).

  12. 12.

    Perhaps the contents of auditory hallucinations, however, are explainable in such terms (Lane and Northoff 2012). Auditory hallucinations can be the sound of one’s own voice, as in “thought broadcast” (Pawar and Spence 2003), or they could be the voices of someone familiar or someone unknown (David 2004). The model proposed here suggests that the difference among these three types might be due to self-related processing. For a novel hypothesis of auditory verbal hallucinations that touches upon some related issues, see, Northoff and Qin (2011) and Northoff (2013a, p. 349).

  13. 13.

    Italics not contained in original.

  14. 14.

    Marcel does observe that it is possible that stimulation of the thalamus causes both the action and an intention, but patients never reported an “urge to do the action.” This leaves only the possibility that an unconscious intention was triggered by the stimulus, but there is no evidence to support this claim.

  15. 15.

    Italics not contained in the original.

References

  • Aboitiz, F., Carrasco, X., Schröter, C., Zaidel, D., Zaidel, E., & Lavados, M. (2003). The alien hand syndrome: Classification of forms reported and discussion of a new condition. Neurological Sciences, 24(4), 252–257.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Auvray, M., Myin, E., & Spence, C. (2010). The sensory-discriminative and affective-motivational aspects of pain. Neuroscience & Biobehavioral Reviews, 34(2), 214–223.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baars, B. J. (2007). Attention and consciousness. In B. J. Baars & N. M. Gage (Eds.), Cognition, brain, and consciousness, second edition: Introduction to cognitive neuroscience (pp. 225–254). New York: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baars, B. J., Ramsøy, T. Z., & Laureys, S. (2003). Brain, conscious experience and the observing self. Trends in Neurosciences, 26(12), 671–675.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barbeau, E., Joubert, S., & Poncet, M. (2004). A single case-study of diagnostic dyspraxia. Brain and Cognition, 54(3), 215–217.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bayne, T. (2010). The unity of consciousness. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bayne, T. (2011). The sense of agency. In F. Macpherson (Ed.), The senses: Classic and contemporary philosophical perspectives (pp. 355–374). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berthier, M., Starkstein, S., & Leiguarda, R. (1988). Asymbolia for pain: A sensory-limbic disconnection syndrome. Annals of Neurology, 24, 41–49.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blakemore, S.-J., Frith, C. D., & Wolpert, D. M. (1999). Spatio-temporal prediction modulates the perception of self-produced stimuli. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 11(5), 551–559.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blakemore, S.-J., Frith, C. D., & Wolpert, D. M. (2000a). Why can’t you tickle yourself? NeuroReport, 11, R11–R16.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blakemore, S.-J., Smith, J., Steel, R., Johnstone, E., & Frith, C. (2000b). The perception of self-produced sensory stimuli in patients with auditory hallucinations and passivity experiences: Evidence for a breakdown of self-monitoring. Psychological Medicine, 30(5), 1131–1139.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bor, D. (2012). The ravenous brain: How the new science of consciousness explains our insatiable search for meaning. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bortolotti, L. (2010). Delusions and other irrational beliefs. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cahill, C., & Frith, C. (1996). False perceptions or false beliefs? Hallucinations and delusions in schizophrenia. In P. W. Halligan & J. C. Marshall (Eds.), Method in madness: Case studies in cognitive neuropsychiatry (pp. 267–291). New York: Psychology Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carruthers, P. (2000). Phenomenal consciousness: A naturalistic theory. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Churchland, P. S. (2002). Brain-wise: Studies in neurophilosophy. Cambridge: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A., Anderson, M. L., Block, N., Bowman, H., Bridgeman, B., Buckingham, G., et al. (2013). Whatever next? Predictive brains, situated agents, and the future of cognitive science. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 36(3), 181–204.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Craig, A. D. (2009). How do you feel—now? The anterior insula and human awareness. Nature Reviews: Neuroscience, 10(1), 59–70.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Crick, F., & Koch, C. (2003). A framework for consciousness. Nature Neuroscience, 6(2), 119–126.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • David, A. S. (2004). The cognitive neuropsychiatry of auditory verbal hallucinations: An overview. Cognitive Neuropsychiatry, 9(1/2), 107–123.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davies, M. (2000). Interaction without reduction: The relationship between personal and sub-personal levels of description. Mind & Society, 1(2), 87–105.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • de Pinedo-Garcia, M., & Noble, J. (2008). Beyond persons: Extending the personal/subpersonal distinction to non-rational animals and artificial agents. Biology and Philosophy, 23(1), 87–100.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Edelman, G. M., Gally, J. A., & Baars, B. J. (2011). Biology of consciousness. Frontiers in Psychology, 2, 1–7.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ellis, H. D., & Lewis, M. B. (2001). Capgras delusion: A window on face recognition. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 5(4), 149–156.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feinberg, T. E. (2009). From axons to identity: Neurological explorations of the nature of the self. New York: W. W. Norton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fitzgibbon, B. M., Giummarra, M. J., Georgiou-Karistianis, N., Enticott, P. G., & Bradshaw, J. L. (2010). Shared pain: From empathy to synaesthesia. Neuroscience and Biobehavioral Reviews, 34(4), 500–512.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frith, C. (2005). The self in action: Lessons from delusions of control. Consciousness and Cognition, 14(4), 752–770.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frith, C. D., Blakemore, S.-J., & Wolpert, D. M. (2000). Explaining the symptoms of schizophrenia: Abnormalities in the awareness of action. Brain Research Reviews, 31(2/3), 357–363.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Friston, K. (2009). The free-energy principle: A rough guide to the brain? Trends in Cognitive Science, 13(7), 293–301.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2012). First-person perspective and immunity to error through misidentification. In S. Miguens & G. Preyer (Eds.), Consciousness and subjectivity (pp. 187–214). Heusenstamm: Ontos.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grahek, N. (2007). Feeling pain and being in pain (2nd ed.). Cambridge: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gray, J. (2004). Consciousness: Creeping up on the hard problem. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haggard, P., Clark, S., & Kalogeras, J. (2002). Voluntary action and conscious awareness. Nature Neuroscience, 5(4), 382–385.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, C. G. (1965). Aspects of scientific explanation and other essays in the philosophy of science. New York: The Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hirjack, D., & Fuchs, T. (2010). Delusions of technical alien control: A phenomenological description of three cases. Psychopathology, 43(2), 96–103.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hohwy, J. (2013). The predictive mind. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Jones, E. G. (2007). The thalamus (2nd ed.). New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klein, S. B. (2013a). The two selves: Their metaphysical commitments and functional independence. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Klein, S. B. (2013b). Making the case that episodic recollection is attributable to operations occurring at retrieval rather than to content stored in a dedicated subsystem of long-term memory. Frontiers in Behavioral Neuroscience, 7(3), 1–14. doi:10.3389/fnbeh.2013.00003.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klein, S. B., & Nichols, S. (2012). Memory and the sense of personal identity. Mind, 121(483), 677–702.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Koch, C. (2004). The quest for consciousness: A neurobiological approach. Englewood: Roberts and Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kühn, S., Brass, M., & Haggard, P. (2013). Feeling in control: Neural correlates of experience of agency. Cortex, 49(7), 1935–1942.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lane, T. (2012). Toward an explanatory framework for mental ownership. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 11(2), 251–286.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lane, T., & Liang, C. (2008). Higher-order thought and the problem of radical confabulation. Southern Journal of Philosophy, 46(1), 69–98.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lane, T., & Liang, C. (2010). Mental ownership and higher-order thought. Analysis, 70(3), 496–501.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lane, T., & Liang, C. (2011). Self-consciousness and immunity. Journal of Philosophy, 108(2), 78–99.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lane, T., & Northoff, G. (2012, July). Mineness, Minimal Self, and Self-Related Processing. Paper presented at the 16th Annual Meeting of the Association for the Scientific Study of Consciousness. Brighton, UK.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lane, T., Yeh, S., & Chang, A. (2013, July). Switching Attention to the Rubber Hand. Paper presented at the 17th Annual Meeting of the Association for the Scientific Study of Consciousness, San Diego, CA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lau, H., & Rosenthal, D. (2011). Empirical support for higher-order theories of conscious awareness. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 15(8), 365–373.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marcel, A. (2003). The sense of agency: Awareness and ownership of action. In J. Roessler & N. Eilan (Eds.), Agency and self-awareness: Issues in philosophy and psychology (pp. 48–93). Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Martin, J.-R., & Pacherie, E. (2013). Out of nowhere: Thought insertion, ownership and context-integration. Consciousness and Cognition, 22(1), 111–122.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, J. (1994). Mind and world. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mellor, C. S. (1970). First-rank symptoms of schizophrenia. British Journal of Psychiatry, 117(536), 15–23.

    Google Scholar 

  • Metzinger, T. (2003). Being no one: The self-model theory of subjectivity. Cambridge: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Miller, M. B., Sinnott-Armstrong, W., Young, L., King, D., Paggi, A., Fabri, M., et al. (2010). Abnormal moral reasoning in complete and partial callosotomy patients. Neuropsychologia, 48(7), 2215–2220.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moore, J. W., & Obhi, S. S. (2012). Intentional binding and the sense of agency: A review. Consciousness and Cognition, 21(1), 546–561.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moore, J. W., Teufel, C., Subramaniam, N., Davis, G., & Fletcher, P. C. (2013). Attribution of intentional causation influences the perception of observed movements: Behavioral evidence and neural correlates. Frontiers in Psychology, 4, 23. doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2013.00023.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mullins, S., & Spence, S. A. (2003). Re-examining thought insertion: Semi-structured literature review and conceptual analysis. British Journal of Psychiatry, 182, 293–298.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nordgaard, J., Arnfred, S. M., Handest, P., & Parnas, J. (2008). The diagnostic status of first rank symptoms. Schizophrenia Bulletin, 34(1), 137–154.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Northoff, G. (2013a). Unlocking the brain: Vol. 2. Consciousness. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Northoff, G. (2013b). Unlocking the brain: Vol. 1. Coding. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Northoff, G., & Bermpohl, F. (2004). Cortical midline structures and the self. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 8(3), 102–107.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Northoff, G., & Panksepp, J. (2008). The trans-species concept of self and the subcortical-cortical midline system. Trends in Cognitive Science, 12(7), 259–264.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Northoff, G., & Qin, P. (2011). How can the brain’s resting state activity generate hallucinations? A “resting state hypothesis” of auditory verbal hallucinations. Schizophrenia Research, 127, 202–214.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Northoff, G., Lane, T., & Yen, N. (2014). Pre-stimulus neural activity predicts self-relatedness judgments in healthy subjects: A multi-modal study. Unpublished manuscript.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pacherie, E. (2011). Self-agency. In S. Gallagher (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of the self (pp. 442–464). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pawar, A. V., & Spence, S. A. (2003). Defining thought broadcast: Semi-structured literature review. British Journal of Psychiatry, 183, 287–291.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Prinz, J. (2012a). Waiting for the self. In J.-L. Liu & J. Perry (Eds.), Consciousness and the Self: New essays (pp. 123–149). New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prinz, J. (2012b). The conscious brain: How attention engenders experience. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Obhi, S. S., & Hall, P. (2011). Sense of agency and intentional binding in joint action. Experimental Brain Research, 211(3/4), 655–662.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ochsner, K. N., Zaki, J., Hanelin, J., Ludlow, D. H., Knierim, K., Ramachanran, T., et al. (2008). Your pain or mine? Common and distinct neural systems supporting the perception of pain in self and other. Social Cognitive and Affective Neuroscience, 3(2), 144–160.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Qin, P., & Northoff, G. (2011). How is our self related to midline regions and the default-mode network? NeuroImage, 57(3), 1221–1233.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Raichle, M. E. (2010). Two views of brain function. Trends in Cognitive Science, 14(4), 180–190.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rosenthal, D. M. (2002). Explaining consciousness. In D. J. Chalmers (Ed.), Philosophy of mind: Classical and contemporary readings (pp. 406–421). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosenthal, D. M. (2005). Consciousness and mind. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosenthal, D. M. (2008). Consciousness and its function. Neuropsychologia, 46(3), 829–840.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sass, L. A., & Parnas, J. (2003). Schizophrenia, consciousness, and the self. Schizophrenia Bulletin, 29(3), 427–444.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schooler, J. W., Smallwood, J., Christoff, K., Handy, T. C., Reichle, E. D., & Sayette, M. A. (2011). Meta-awareness, perceptual decoupling and the wandering mind. Trends in Cognitive Science, 15(7), 319–326.

    Google Scholar 

  • Seth, A. K., Suzuki, K., & Critchley, H. D. (2012). An interoceptive predictive coding model of conscious presence. Frontiers in Psychology, 2, 395.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shea, N. (2013). Neural mechanisms of decision-making and the personal level. In K. W. M. Fulford, M. Davies, R. G. T. Gipps, G. Graham, J. Z. Sadler & G. Stanghellini (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of philosophy and psychiatry (pp. 1063–1082). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shoemaker, S. (1994). Self-knowledge and “inner Sense”: Lecture I: The object perception model. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 54(2), 249–269.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sierra, M. (2009). Depersonalization: A new look at a neglected syndrome. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sorensen, R. (2007). The vanishing point: A model of the self as an absence. Monist, 90(3), 432–456.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sperduti, M., Pieron, M., Leboyer, M., & Zalla, T. (2013, July 24). Altered pre-reflective sense of agency in autism spectrum disorders as revealed by reduced intentional binding. Journal of Autism and Developmental Disorders, 44(2), 343–352. doi:10.1007/s10803–013-1891-y. (http://link.springer.com/article/10.1007/s10803–013-1891-y.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Stephens, G. L., & Graham, G. (2000). When self-consciousness breaks: Alien voices and inserted thoughts. Cambridge: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stone, J. L., & Goodrich, J. T. (2006). The craniopagus malformation: Classification and implications for surgical separation. Brain, 129(5), 1084–1095.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Swiney, L., & Sousa, P. (2013). When our thoughts are not our own: Investigating agency misattribution using the Mind-to-Mind paradigm. Consciousness and Cognition, 22(2), 589–602.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tsakiris, M., Schütz-Bosbach, S., & Gallagher, S. (2007). On agency and body-ownership: Phenomenological and neurocognitive reflections. Consciousness and Cognition, 16(3), 645–660.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Uddin, L. Q. (2011). Brain connectivity and the self: The case of cerebral disconnection. Consciousness and Cognition, 20(1), 94–98.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Verleger, R., Binkofski, F., Friedrich, M., Sedlmeier, P., & Kömpf, D. (2011). Anarchic-hand syndrome: ERP reflections of lost control over the right hemisphere. Brain and Cognition, 77(1), 138–150.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Voss, M., Moore, J., Hauser, M., Gallinat, J., Heinz, A., & Haggard, P. (2010). Altered awareness of action in schizophrenia: A specific deficit in predicting action consequences. Brain, 133(10), 3104–3112.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wegner, D. (2002). The illusion of conscious will. Cambridge: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wohlschläger, A., Haggard, P., Gesierich, B., & Prinz, W. (2003). The perceived onset time of self-and other-generated actions. Psychological Science, 14(6), 586–591.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zahn, R., Talazko, J., & Ebert, D. (2008). Loss of the sense of self-ownership for perceptions of objects in a case of right inferior temporal, parieto-occipital and precentral hypometabolism. Psychopathology, 41(6), 397–402.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zihl, J., von Cramon, D., & Mai, N. (1983). Selective disturbance of movement vision after bilateral brain damage. Brain, 106(2), 313–340.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I express my heartfelt gratitude to Ellie Hua Wang and to Tzu-Wei Hung for their constructive comments on previous versions of this manuscript. For much useful discussion, I am also grateful to the many other participants in Academia Sinica’s International Conference on Language and Action, Taipei, Taiwan (September 17–18, 2013). Funding for this research was, in part, provided by National Science Council of Taiwan research grants, 100-2410-H-038-009-MY3 and 102-2420-H-038-001-MY3.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Timothy Lane .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2014 Springer Science+Business Media Singapore

About this paper

Cite this paper

Lane, T. (2014). When Actions Feel Alien—an Explanatory Model. In: Hung, TW. (eds) Communicative Action. Springer, Singapore. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-981-4585-84-2_4

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics