Skip to main content

Theoretical and Practical Justifications for Popper’s Non-justificationism

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Childhood, Philosophy and Open Society

Part of the book series: Education in the Asia-Pacific Region: Issues, Concerns and Prospects ((EDAP,volume 22))

  • 804 Accesses

Abstract

Popper’s non-justificationism or falsificationism is justified on the grounds that it not only solves, theoretically, the problem of the bounds of reason in the form of comprehensively critical rationalism, but also influences, practically, the research work of scientists from diverse fields over a long span of time. The implementation of Popper’s falsificationist epistemology means exposing to criticism various philosophical presuppositions that work against criticism, including the doctrine that truth is manifest, the demand for precision in concepts as a prerequisite for criticism, essentialism, instrumentalism, and conventionalism; it also means combating the confirmation bias through such educational means as helping teachers and students to acquire an awareness of its pervasiveness and various guises, teaching them to think of several alternative hypotheses simultaneously in seeking explanation of phenomena, and encouraging them to assess evidence objectively in the formation and evaluation of hypotheses. With regard to the feasibility of teaching students to falsify, it appears high if teachers adopt relatively simple inference tasks, while creating an opportunity for students to collaborate with each other and lowering the normativity of the learning environment. As for the utility of doing so, although disconfirmation might be an effective heuristic when students cannot appeal to an outside authority to test their hypotheses, it appears not to be a universally effective strategy for solving reasoning problems. In contrast, confirmation seems not to be completely counterproductive and might be a useful heuristic, especially in the early stages of solving by hypothesis a complex inference problem.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    This empiricist view of geometry is not without its difficulties, a grave one of which is that it is impossible to find geometric objects, like points and lines, in experience exactly as geometry conceives them (Torretti, 1984).

  2. 2.

    The liar paradox is generated by a sentence that, directly or indirectly, asserts its own falsity. A typical example is: (L) This sentence is false. In this case, the argument runs as follows: if (L) is true, then what it asserts is so; but what it asserts is that (L) is false, hence (L) is false. Yet, if (L) is false, then what it asserts is not so; but what it asserts is that (L) is false, hence (L) is true. In other words, the paradox arises because it seems possible to prove that (L) is true if and only if it is false, and vice versa.

  3. 3.

    Grelling’s paradox is concerned with the fact that some words are self-describing, or autological (e.g. “short” is a short word, “English” is an English word) while other words are non-self-describing, or heterological (e.g. “long” is not a long word, “Chinese” is not a Chinese word). It arises when we consider whether the word “heterological” is heterological: on one hand, if “heterological” is a heterological word, then it is clearly autological (by definition), yet heterological (by assumption); on the other hand, if “heterological” is not a heterological word, then it is clearly heterological (by definition), yet autological (by assumption). In either case, a contradiction results.

  4. 4.

    Apart from Russell’s and Tarski’s approaches to such semantical paradox, various strategies, like Kripke’s concept of grounding, Van Fraassen’s device of supervaluations, and Gupta’s theory of revision rule, have been developed in recent decades to resolve it (Martin, 1984).

References

  • Akeroyd, F. M. (1985). The relationship between Popper’s philosophy and the acceptance of the vitamin theory: A case study of the methodology of scientific research. Journal of Biological Education, 19, 224–226.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Annas, J., & Barnes, J. (1994). Introduction. In E. Sextus (Ed.), Outlines of scepticism (J. Annas & J. Barnes, Trans., pp. ix–xv). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Artigas, M. (1999). Popper and critical rationalism: About Karl Popper’s comments in Kyoto, 1992. In I. Slade (Ed.), The ethical nature of Karl Popper’s theory of knowledge: Including Popper’s unpublished comments on Bartley and critical rationalism (pp. 15–102). Bern, Germany: Peter Lang.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baghramian, M. (2004). Relativism. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bailey, A. (2002). Sextus Empiricus and Pyrrhonean scepticism. Oxford, England: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bailey, R. (2000). Education in the open society: Karl Popper and schooling. Aldershot, England: Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baron, J. (1995). Myside bias in thinking about abortion. Thinking and Reasoning, 1(3), 221–235.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bartley, W. W., III. (1976). Critical study: The philosophy of Karl Popper [Part I: Biology and evolutionary epistemology]. Philosophia, 6(3–4), 463–494.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bartley, W. W., III. (1980). On the criticizability of logic: A reply to A. A. Derksen. Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 10, 67–77.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bartley, W. W., III. (1982). Critical study: The philosophy of Karl Popper [Part III: Rationality, criticism, and logic]. Philosophia, 11(1–2), 121–221.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bartley, W. W., III. (1987a). A refutation of the alleged refutation of comprehensively critical rationalism. In G. Radnitzky & W. W. Bartley III (Eds.), Evolutionary epistemology, rationality, and the sociology of knowledge (pp. 313–341). La Salle, IL: Open Court.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bartley, W. W., III. (1987b). Theories of rationality. In G. Radnitzky & W. W. Bartley III (Eds.), Evolutionary epistemology, rationality, and the sociology of knowledge (pp. 205–214). La Salle, IL: Open Court.

    Google Scholar 

  • Butera, F., Caverni, J.-P., & Rossi, S. (2005). Interaction with a high- versus low- competence influence source in inductive reasoning. The Journal of Social Psychology, 145, 173–190.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carruthers, P. (2004). The nature of the mind: An introduction. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dawson, E., Gilovich, T., & Regan, D. T. (2002). Motivated reasoning and performance on the Wason selection task. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 28, 1379–1387.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Derksen, A. A. (1980). The failure of comprehensively critical rationalism. Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 10, 51–66.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eccles, J. C. (1974). The world of objective knowledge. In P. A. Schilpp (Ed.), The philosophy of Karl Popper (pp. 349–370). La Salle, IL: Open Court.

    Google Scholar 

  • Einhorn, H. J., & Hogarth, R. M. (1978). Confidence in judgment: Persistence of the illusion of validity. Psychological Review, 85, 395–416.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Einstein, A. (1982). Ideas and opinions. New York: Crown.

    Google Scholar 

  • Evans, J. S. B. T. (1989). Bias in human reasoning: Causes and consequences. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Federspil, G., & Vettor, R. (2000). Can scientific medicine incorporate alternative medicine? The Journal of Alternative and Complementary Medicine, 6, 241–244.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. D., Fodor, J. A., & Garrett, M. F. (1975). The psychological unreality of semantic representations. Linguistic Inquiry, 4, 515–531.

    Google Scholar 

  • Friedrich, J. (1993). Primary error detection and minimization (PEDMIN) strategies in social cognition: A reinterpretation of confirmation bias phenomena. Psychological Review, 100, 298–319.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fugelsang, J. A., Stein, C. B., Green, A. E., & Dunbar, K. N. (2004). Theory and data interactions of the scientific mind: Evidence from the molecular and the cognitive laboratory. Canadian Journal of Experimental Psychology, 58, 86–95.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gardner, M. (1977). On playing New Eleusis, the game that stimulates the search for truth. Scientific American, 237(4), 18–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gattei, S. (2002). The ethical nature of Karl Popper’s solution to the problem of rationality. Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 32, 240–266.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gettier, E. (1963). Is justified true belief knowledge? Analysis, 23, 121–123.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gomory, T. (2002). Social work method: Karl Popper “justified”, induction (justification) falsified – A response to Eileen Munro. Journal of Social Work Education, 38, 475–481.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gorman, M. E. (1986). How the possibility of error affects falsification on a task that models scientific problem solving. British Journal of Psychology, 77, 85–96.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gorman, M. E. (1992). Experimental simulations of falsification. In M. T. Keane & K. J. Gilhooly (Eds.), Advances in the psychology of thinking (Vol. 1, pp. 147–176). London: Harvester Wheatsheaf.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gorman, M. E. (1995). Hypothesis testing. In S. E. Newstead & J. S. B. T. Evans (Eds.), Perspectives on thinking and reasoning: Essays in honour of Peter Wason (pp. 217–240). Hove, England: Lawrence Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gorman, M. E., & Gorman, M. E. (1984). A comparison of disconfirmatory, confirmatory and control strategies on Wason’s 2-4-6 task. The Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology, 36A, 629–648.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gorman, M. E., Gorman, M. E., Latta, R. M., & Cunningham, G. (1984). How disconfirmatory, confirmatory and combined strategies affect group problem solving. British Journal of Psychology, 75, 65–79.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gorman, M. E., Stafford, A., & Gorman, M. E. (1987). Disconfirmation and dual hypotheses on a more difficult version of Wason’s 2-4-6 task. Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology, 39A, 1–28.

    Google Scholar 

  • Greenwald, A. G. (1980). The totalitarian ego: Fabrication and revision of personal history. American Psychologist, 35, 603–618.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haack, S. (1993). Evidence and inquiry: Towards reconstruction in epistemology. Oxford, England: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hayek, F. A. (1952). The sensory order: An inquiry into the foundations of theoretical psychology. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Henrion, M., & Fischhoff, B. (1986). Assessing uncertainty in physical constants. American Journal of Physics, 54, 791–798.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Karmiloff-Smith, A., & Inhelder, B. (1975). If you want to get ahead, get a theory. Cognition, 3, 195–212.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Klayman, J., & Ha, Y.-W. (1987). Confirmation, disconfirmation, and information in hypothesis testing. Psychological Review, 94, 211–228.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mahoney, M. J., & Kimper, T. P. (1976). From ethics to logics: A survey of scientists. In M. J. Mahoney (Ed.), Scientist as subject: The psychological imperative (pp. 187–193). Cambridge, MA: Ballinger.

    Google Scholar 

  • Martin, R. L. (Ed.). (1984). Recent essays on truth and the Liar paradox. Oxford, England: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Matlin, M. W., & Stang, D. J. (1978). The Pollyanna principle: Selectivity in language, memory and thought. Cambridge, MA: Shenkman.

    Google Scholar 

  • Miller, D. (1994). Critical rationalism: A restatement and defence. La Salle, IL: Open Court.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moshman, D., & Geil, M. (1998). Collaborative reasoning: Evidence for collective rationality. Thinking and Reasoning, 4, 231–248.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mulkay, M., & Gilbert, G. N. (1981). Putting philosophy to work: Karl Popper’s influence on scientific practice. Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 11, 389–407.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Munro, E. (2002). The role of theory in social work research: A further contribution to the debate. Journal of Social Work Education, 38, 461–470.

    Google Scholar 

  • Musgrave, A. (1993). Common sense, science and scepticism: A historical introduction to the theory of knowledge. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mynatt, C. R., Doherty, M. E., & Tweney, R. D. (1977). Confirmation bias in a simulated research environment: An experimental study of scientific inference. Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology, 29, 85–95.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mynatt, C. R., Doherty, M. E., & Tweney, R. D. (1978). Consequences of confirmation and disconfirmation in a simulated research environment. Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology, 30, 395–406.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nickerson, R. S. (1998). Confirmation bias: A ubiquitous phenomenon in many guises. Review of General Psychology, 2, 175–220.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Notturno, M. A. (2000). Science and the open society: The future of Karl Popper’s philosophy. Budapest, Hungary: Central European University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Poletiek, F. H. (1996). Paradoxes of falsification. The Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology, 49A, 447–462.

    Google Scholar 

  • Polya, G. (1954). Mathematics and plausible reasoning: Induction and analogy in mathematics (Vol. 1). Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. R. (1966). The open society and its enemies: The high tide of prophecy (5th ed., Vol. 2). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. R. (1979). Objective knowledge: An evolutionary approach (Rev. ed.). Hong Kong: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. R. (1980). The logic of scientific discovery (4th ed.). London: Unwin Hyman.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. R. (1983). Induction. In W. W. Bartley, III (Ed.), Realism and the aim of science (pp. 11–158). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. R. (1989). Conjectures and refutations: The growth of scientific knowledge (5th ed.). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. R. (1996). Introduction. In M. A. Notturno (Ed.), The myth of the framework: In defence of science and rationality (pp. xii–xiii). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. R. (1999). Workshop seminar in Kyoto. In M. Artigas (Ed.), The ethical nature of Karl Popper’s theory of knowledge: Including Popper’s unpublished comments on Bartley and critical rationalism (pp. 29–33). Bern, Germany: Peter Lang.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. R. (2002a). The poverty of historicism. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. R. (2002b). Unended quest: An intellectual autobiography (2nd ed.). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Post, J. F. (1987). A Gödelian theorem for theories of rationality. In G. Radnitzky & W. W. Bartley III (Eds.), Evolutionary epistemology, rationality, and the sociology of knowledge (pp. 253–267). La Salle, IL: Open Court.

    Google Scholar 

  • Price, D. J. de S. (1963). Little science, big science. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pyszczynski, T., & Greenberg, J. (1987). Toward an integration of cognitive and motivational perspectives on social inference: A biased hypothesis-testing model. In L. Berkowitz (Ed.), Advances in experimental social psychology (Vol. 20, pp. 297–340). New York: Academic Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Radnitzky, G. (1987). In defense of self-applicable critical rationalism. In G. Radnitzky & W. W. Bartley III (Eds.), Evolutionary epistemology, rationality, and the sociology of knowledge (pp. 279–312). La Salle, IL: Open Court.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sankey, D. (1999, December). Classrooms as safe places to be wrong. Paper presented at the UNESCO-ACEID International Conference, Bangkok, Thailand.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sextus, E. (1994). Outlines of scepticism (J. Annas & J. Barnes, Trans.). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sovacool, B. (2005). Falsification and demarcation in astronomy and cosmology. Bulletin of Science, Technology & Society, 25, 53–62.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stenning, K., & van Lambalgen, M. (2004). The natural history of hypotheses about the selection task: Towards a philosophy of science for investigating human reasoning. In K. Manktelow & M. C. Chung (Eds.), Psychology of reasoning: Theoretical and historical perspectives (pp. 127–156). Hove, England: Psychology Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Torretti, R. (1984). Philosophy of geometry from Riemann to Poincaré. Dordrecht, the Netherlands: D. Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tweney, R. D. (1989). A framework for the cognitive psychology of science. In B. Gholson, W. R. Shadish Jr., R. A. Neimeyer, & A. C. Houts (Eds.), Psychology of science (pp. 342–366). Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tweney, R. D., & Chitwood, S. T. (1995). Scientific reasoning. In S. E. Newstead & J. S. B. T. Evans (Eds.), Perspectives on thinking and reasoning: Essays in honour of Peter Wason (pp. 241–260). Hove, England: Lawrence Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tweney, R. D., & Doherty, M. E. (1983). Rationality and the psychology of inference. Synthese, 57, 139–161.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tweney, R. D., Doherty, M. E., Worner, W. J., Pliske, D. B., Mynatt, C. R., Gross, K. A., et al. (1980). Strategies of rule discovery on an inference task. Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology, 32, 109–123.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Fraassen, B. C. (2002). The empirical stance. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vartanian, O., Martindale, C., & Kwiatkowski, J. (2003). Creativity and inductive reasoning: The relationship between divergent thinking and performance on Wason’s 2-4-6 task. The Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology, 56A, 1–15.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wason, P. C. (1960). On the failure to eliminate hypotheses in a conceptual task. Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology, 12, 129–140.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wason, P. C. (1961). Response to affirmative and negative binary statements. British Journal of Psychology, 52, 133–142.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wason, P. C. (1966). Reasoning. In B. M. Foss (Ed.), New horizons in psychology (Vol. 1, pp. 135–151). Harmondsworth, England: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Watkins, J. W. N. (1971). CCR: A refutation. Philosophy, 46, 56–61.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Watkins, J. W. N. (1987). Comprehensively critical rationalism: A retrospect. In G. Radnitzky & W. W. Bartley III (Eds.), Evolutionary epistemology, rationality, and the sociology of knowledge (pp. 269–277). La Salle, IL: Open Court.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wetherick, N. E. (1962). Eliminative and enumerative behaviour in a conceptual task. Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology, 14, 246–249.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2013 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Lam, CM. (2013). Theoretical and Practical Justifications for Popper’s Non-justificationism. In: Childhood, Philosophy and Open Society. Education in the Asia-Pacific Region: Issues, Concerns and Prospects, vol 22. Springer, Singapore. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-981-4451-06-2_2

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics