Skip to main content

Assessing Objections to Compulsory Voting in Australia

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
A Century of Compulsory Voting in Australia

Abstract

This chapter considers several objections to compulsory in Australia: that compulsory voting unacceptably abridges individual liberty; that it is unnecessary for high electoral turnout; that it is undemocratic; that it violates the ‘right not to vote’; that it has a detrimental effect upon the behaviour and composition of Australia’s political parties; and that it mobilises large numbers of disengaged citizens, with negative consequences for Australian democracy. The chapter provides a critical assessment of these objections and concludes that none of them comes anywhere close to showing that compulsory voting in Australia ought to be repealed.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 139.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 139.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. 1.

    Minchin’s views are echoed by some in the scholarly literature. See e.g. Ciccone (2002, pp. 347–350), Swenson (2007, pp. 536–537), and Saunders (2017, 2018).

  2. 2.

    Some proponents of compulsory voting have sought to respond to this line of objection by appeal to non-standard conceptions of liberty. See esp. Lardy (2004), Hill (2014, pp. 190–191), and Elliott (2017). For a critique of these arguments, see Umbers (Unpublished MS).

  3. 3.

    Moreover, as Bonotti (in this volume) points out, compulsory voting may also help ensure that officials offer appropriate public justification for other liberty-abridging policies.

  4. 4.

    Many studies have found similar results. See e.g. Husted and Kenny (1997), Aidt and Dallal (2008), and Abou-Chadi and Orlowski (2015).

  5. 5.

    This evidence also constitutes a powerful riposte to the charge that compulsory voting leads political parties to be less responsive to the worse-off (see e.g. Barry 2013, p. 39).

  6. 6.

    Many studies have found similar results. See e.g. O’Toole and Stroble (1995), Mueller and Stratmann (2003), Bechtel et al. (2016), and Carey and Horiuchi (2017).

  7. 7.

    Others have argued that the wrongness of free-riding lends support to compulsory voting for other reasons (see esp. Wertheimer 1975; Lijphart 1997, p. 11; Engelen 2007, p. 32).

  8. 8.

    It is also worth noting that, in at least some cases, the abolition of compulsory voting has been associated with a steep decline in electoral participation. In 1988, for example, turnout in national elections in Venezuela was 81.7%. Penalties for abstention were abolished for the subsequent 1993 election, at which turnout was around 60% (Birch 2009, p. 88).

  9. 9.

    It is worth noting that liberty-based accounts of the value of democracy are highly controversial. See esp. Christiano (1996, pp. 15–46).

  10. 10.

    Interestingly, Lacroix (2007) has argued that compulsory voting is compatible with individual liberty on the grounds that political participation is necessary for citizens to enjoy positive freedom. For a powerful critique of this argument, see Brennan (2014, pp. 66–69).

  11. 11.

    See Umbers (2020b) for an overview.

  12. 12.

    This line of argument is echoed in other scholarly pieces critical of compulsory voting, more generally. See, for example, Blomberg (1995, p. 1023); Ciccone (2002, pp. 347–348); Lever (2010, p. 911).

  13. 13.

    Of course, for some citizens $20 may constitute a non-trivial sum of money. There are obvious reforms that would address this issue—e.g. making the fine proportional to citizens’ levels of income and wealth.

  14. 14.

    Though, of course, some political theorists have argued that such arrangements are, indeed, unjust. See esp. Nozick (1974). I think that there are powerful reasons to be sceptical of such arguments—though I cannot explore the issue in depth here.

  15. 15.

    See Engelen (2009, p. 220) for a similar response.

  16. 16.

    See e.g. JSCEM (1997, pp. 25–26).

  17. 17.

    Indeed, it is often argued that this at least partially explains why the major parties in Australia adopted compulsory voting in the first place. See e.g. Miragliotta et al. (2013, p. 147).

  18. 18.

    Others have voiced similar concerns. Don Aitkin (1982, p. 283), for instance, writes that ‘[s]ince the introduction of compulsory voting in 1924 the parties have ceased to regard the building of membership as a vital party function’.

  19. 19.

    Though there is, of course, a large literature on ‘distributive politics’, insights from which might plausibly be brought to bear on this question. For an overview, see Golden and Min (2013).

  20. 20.

    See also Gordon and Segura (1997); Berggren (2001); Shineman (2012, 2018‚ Forthcoming); Carreras (2016); Córdova and Rangel (2017).

Bibliography

  • Abou-Chadi, T., & Orlowski, M. (2015). Political institutions and the distributional consequences of suffrage extension. Political Studies, 63(1), 55–72.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Aidt, T. S., & Dallal, B. (2008). Female voting power: The contribution of women’s suffrage to the growth of social spending in Western Europe (1869–1960). Public Choice, 134, 391–417.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Aitkin, D. (1982). Stability and change in Australian politics (2nd ed.). Canberra, ACT: Australian National University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ANES, The American National Election Studies. (2016). The ANES guide to public opinion and electoral behaviour. Ann Arbor, MI: University of Michigan, Centre for Political Studies.

    Google Scholar 

  • Commonwealth Parliamentary Debates (CPD). (1924, July 17). p. 2183.

    Google Scholar 

  • Commonwealth Parliamentary Debates (CPD). (1993, August 30). Senate, p. 523.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barry, P. (2013, September 1). How compulsory voting subverts democracy. Quadrant, pp. 38–42.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, M. M., Hangartner, D., & Schmid, L. (2016). Does compulsory voting increase support for leftist policy? American Journal of Political Science, 60(3), 752–767.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beitz, C. (1989). Political equality: An essay in democratic theory. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bennett, S. (2005). Compulsory voting in Australian national elections. Canberra, ACT: Australian Parliamentary Library.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berggren, H. M. (2001). Institutional context and reduction of the resource bias in political sophistication. Political Research Quarterly, 54(3), 531–552.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Berlin, I. (1958). Two concepts of liberty. In R. E. Goodin & P. Pettit (Eds.), Contemporary political philosophy: An anthology (2nd ed., pp. 369–386). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Biezen, I. V., Mair, P., & Poguntke, T. (2012). Going, going, … gone? The decline of party membership in contemporary Europe. European Journal of Political Research, 51(1), 24–56.

    Google Scholar 

  • Birch, S. (2009). Full participation: A comparative study of compulsory voting. Manchester: Manchester University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Blais, A., & Rubenson, D. (2013). The source of turnout decline: New values or new contexts? Comparative Political Studies, 46(1), 95–117.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blomberg, J. A. (1995). Protecting the right to vote from voter purge statutes. Fordham Law Review, 64(3), 1015–1050.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brennan, J. (2014). Medicine worse than the disease? Against compulsory voting. In J. Brennan & L. Hill (Eds.), Compulsory voting: For and against (pp. 1–110). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Brett, J. (2019). From secret ballot to democracy sausage: How Australia got compulsory voting. Melbourne, AUS: Text Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Burgmann, V. (1990). Voting just helps encourage them. Herald, 19 February.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cameron, S. M., & McAllister, I. (2016). Trends in Australian political opinion: Results from the Australian election study 1987–2016. Canberra, ACT: Australian National University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carey, J. M., & Horiuchi, Y. (2017). Compulsory voting and income inequality: Evidence for Lijphart’s proposition from Venezuela. Latin American Politics and Society, 59(2), 122–144.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carreras, M. (2016). Compulsory voting and political engagement (beyond the ballot box): A multilevel analysis. Electoral Studies, 43(1), 158–168.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chapman, E. B. (2019). The distinctive value of elections and the case for compulsory voting. American Journal of Political Science, 63(1), 101–112.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chong, A., & Olivera, M. (2008). Does compulsory voting help equalize incomes? Economics & Politics, 20(3), 391–415.

    Google Scholar 

  • Christiano, T. (1996). The rule of the many: Fundamental issues in democratic theory. Boulder, CO: Westview Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Christiano, T. (2008). The constitution of equality: Democratic authority and its limits. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ciccone, A. (2002). The right to vote is not a duty. Hamline Journal of Public Law & Policy, 23, 325–357.

    Google Scholar 

  • Citrin, J., Schickler, E., & Sides, J. (2003). What if everyone voted? Simulating the impact of increased turnout in senate elections. American Journal of Political Science, 47(1), 75–90.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Córdova, A., & Rangel, G. (2017). Addressing the gender gap: The effect of compulsory voting on women’s electoral engagement. Comparative Political Studies, 50(2), 264–290.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Denemark, D. (2000). Partisan pork barrel in parliamentary systems: Australian constituency-level grants. The Journal of Politics, 62(3), 896–915.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Elliott, K. J. (2017). Aid for our purposes: Mandatory voting as precommitment and nudge. The Journal of Politics, 79(2), 656–669.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Engelen, B. (2007). Why compulsory voting can enhance democracy. Acta Politica, 42(1), 23–39.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Engelen, B. (2009). Why liberals can favour compulsory attendance. Politics, 29(3), 218–222.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Forrest, J. (1992). The geography of campaign funding, campaign spending and voting at the New South Wales legislative assembly elections of 1984. The Australian Geographer, 23(1), 66–76.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fowler, A. (2013). Electoral and policy consequences of voter turnout: Evidence from compulsory voting in Australia. Quarterly Journal of Political Science, 8(2), 159–182.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gauja, A. (2015). The state of democracy and representation in Australia. Representation, 51(1), 23–34.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gaus, G. F. (1996). Justificatory liberalism: An essay on epistemology and political theory. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Golden, M., & Min, B. (2013). Distributive politics around the world. Annual Review of Political Science, 16, 73–99.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gordon, S. B., & Segura, G. M. (1997). Cross-national variation in the political sophistication of individuals: Capability or choice? The Journal of Politics, 59(1), 126–147.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hill, L. (2014). Compulsory voting defended. In J. Brennan & L. Hill (Eds.), Compulsory voting: For and against (pp. 111–204). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hill, L. (2015). Does compulsory voting violate a right not to vote? Australian Journal of Political Science, 50(1), 61–72.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hughes, C. A. (1966). Compulsory voting. Politics, 1(2), 81–95.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Husted, T. A., & Kenny, L. W. (1997). The effect of the expansion of the voting franchise on the size of government. Journal of Political Economy, 105(1), 54–82.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jackman, S. (1999). Non-compulsory voting in Australia?: What surveys can (and can’t) tell us. Electoral Studies, 18(1), 29–48.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jackman, S. (2001). Voting: Compulsory. In N. J. Smelser & P. B. Bates (Eds.), International encyclopedia of the social and behavioural sciences (pp. 16314–16318). Amsterdam: Elsevier.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • JSCEM (Joint Standing Committee on Electoral Matters). (1997). Report of the inquiry into all aspects of the conduct of the 1996 federal election and matters related thereto. Australia.

    Google Scholar 

  • Katz, R. S. (1997). Democracy and elections. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kolodny, N. (2014). Rule over none II: Social equality and the justification of democracy. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 42(4), 287–336.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lacroix, J. (2007). A liberal defence of compulsory voting. Politics, 27(3), 190–195.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lardy, H. (2004). Is there a right not to vote? Oxford Journal of Legal Studies, 24(2), 303–321.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leigh, A. (2008). Bringing home the bacon: An empirical analysis of the extent and effects of pork-barreling in Australian politics. Public Choice, 137(1–2), 279–299.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lever, A. (2008). A liberal defence of compulsory voting: Some reasons for scepticism. Politics, 28(1), 61–64.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lever, A. (2010). Compulsory voting: A critical perspective. British Journal of Political Science, 40(4), 897–915.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lever, A., & Volacu, A. (2018). Should voting Be compulsory? Democracy and the ethics of voting. In A. Lever & A. Poama (Eds.), Routledge handbook of ethics & public policy. New York: Routledge.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Lijphart, A. (1997). Unequal participation: Democracy’s unresolved dilemma. American Political Science Review, 91(1), 1–14.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lipsitz, K. (2011). Competitive elections and the American voter. Philadelphia, PA: University of Pennsylvania Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lupia, A., & McCubbins, M. D. (1998). The democratic dilemma: Can citizens learn what they need to know?. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mackerras, M., & McAllister, I. (1999). Compulsory voting, party stability, and electoral advantage in Australia. Electoral Studies, 18(2), 217–233.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Martin, P. S. (2003). Voting’s rewards: Voter turnout, attentive publics, and congressional allocation of federal money. American Journal of Political Science, 47(1), 110–127.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McAllister, I. (2011). The Australian voter: 50 years of change. Sydney, NSW: UNSW Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Miragliotta, N., Errington, W., & Barry, N. (2013). The Australian political system in action (2nd ed.). Australia: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mueller, D. C., & Stratmann, T. (2003). The economic effects of democratic participation. Journal of Public Economics, 87(9–10), 2129–2155.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nozick, R. (1974). Anarchy, state, and utopia. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Toole, F., & Stroble, E. (1995). Compulsory voting and government spending. Economics and Politics, 7(3), 271–280.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Orr, G. (2002). Ballot order: Donkey voting in Australia. Election Law Journal, 1(4), 573–578.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pringle, H. (2012). Compulsory voting in Australia: What is compulsory? Australian Journal of Political Science, 47(3), 427–440.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. (1988). The priority of right and ideas of the good. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 17(4), 251–276.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. (2005). Political liberalism (Expanded ed.). New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rydon, J. (1963). The electorate. In J. Wilkes (Ed.), Forces in Australian politics (pp. 167–204). Sydney: Australian Institute of Political Science and Angus and Robertson.

    Google Scholar 

  • Saunders, B. (2017). A defence of the right not to vote. In E. M. Crookston, D. Killoren, & J. Trerise (Eds.), Ethics in politics: The rights and obligations of individual political agents (pp. 254–268). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Saunders, B. (2018). A further defence of the right not to vote. Res Publica, 24(1), 93–108.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sheppard, J. (2015). Compulsory voting and political knowledge: Testing a ‘compelled engagement’ hypothesis. Electoral Studies, 40(1), 300–307.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shineman, V. A. (2012). Isolating the effect of compulsory voting laws on political sophistication: Exploiting intra-national variation in mandatory voting laws between the Austrian provinces. SSRN. https://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=2147871. Accessed 17 July 2020.

  • Shineman, V. A. (2018). If you mobilize them, they will become informed: experimental evidence that information acquisition is endogenous to costs and incentives to participate. British Journal of Political Science, 48(1), 189–211.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shineman, V. A. (Forthcoming). Compulsory Voting Increases Political Information: Leveraging Intra-National Variation in Compulsory Voting Laws across the Austrian Provinces. Electoral Studies.

    Google Scholar 

  • Singh, S. P. (2015). Compulsory voting and the turnout decision calculus. Political Studies, 63(3), 548–568.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Swenson, K. M. (2007). Sticks, carrots, donkey votes, and true choice: A rationale for abolishing compulsory voting in Australia. Minnesota Journal of International Law, 16(2), 525–552.

    Google Scholar 

  • Umbers, L. M. (2020a). Compulsory voting: A defence. British Journal of Political Science, 50(4), 1037–1324.

    Google Scholar 

  • Umbers, L. M. (2020b). Enfranchising the youth. Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy, 23(6), 732–755.

    Google Scholar 

  • Umbers, L. M. (Unpublished MS). Coercion, compulsory voting, and liberty.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vowles, J., McMillan, K., Barker, F., Curtin, J., Hayward, J., Greaves, L., & Crothers, C. (2017). New Zealand election study. http://www.nzes.org/exec/show/2017. Accessed 21 July 2020.

  • Waldron, J. (1987). Theoretical foundations of liberalism. The Philosophical Quarterly, 37(147), 127–150.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ward, H., & John, P. (1999). Targeting benefits for electoral gain: Constituency marginality and the distribution of grants to English local authorities. Political Studies, 47(1), 32–52.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wertheimer, A. (1975). In defense of compulsory voting. In J. R. Pennock & J. V. Chapman (Eds.), Nomos XVI: Participation in Politics (pp. 276–296). New York: Leiber-Atherton.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Lachlan Montgomery Umbers .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2021 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Singapore Pte Ltd.

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Umbers, L.M. (2021). Assessing Objections to Compulsory Voting in Australia. In: Bonotti, M., Strangio, P. (eds) A Century of Compulsory Voting in Australia. Elections, Voting, Technology. Palgrave Macmillan, Singapore. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-981-33-4025-1_4

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics