Skip to main content

Behavioral Finance and Corporate Finance

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Corporate Finance: A Systematic Approach

Part of the book series: Springer Texts in Business and Economics ((STBE))

  • 812 Accesses

Abstract

The seminal works by Daniel Kahneman, Amos Tversky and Richard Thaler have inspired many researches in behavioral economics. Behavioral economics and behavioral finance incorporate the concepts and methods in psychology science into traditional economics (finance).

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 119.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Tversky and Kahneman’s (1986, p. S268-S269) medical treatment of tumor experiment (Case 3) is exactly the same as Example 11.1 except that the subjects are not required to make a choice before the game starts. Tversky et al. argue that people made mistakes by not using the probabilities: 0.25 × 0.80 = 0.20 and 0.25 × 1.0 = 0.25 and claim that it is ‘pseudocertainty effect’. This is wrong since the probability 0.25 of the testing result that the tumor is treatable in the first stage is not up to the subjects to decide. If the tumor is not treatable, i.e., the subject cannot survive, it will be meaningless to ask which choice (treatment) the subject will choose in the second stage.

  2. 2.

    See also Thaler (1980).

  3. 3.

    For the second half of the season, Arkes et al. find that all the groups attend about the same number of plays. However, this may be due to that people in the second half of the season had new choices which can produce higher net utilities rather than Arkes et al.’s ‘diminishing sunk cost effect’. Gourville and Soman’s (1998) experiment of gym memberships and attendance also finds that the price paid for an item has a diminishing effect on consumption behavior as time goes on, and there was a substantial spike in attendance following payment.

  4. 4.

    See Appendix A for a real story of the sunk cost fallacy.

  5. 5.

    Buchanan (1969, p. 28) introduces Ronald Coase’s definition of opportunity cost as: “Any profit opportunity that is within the realm of possibility but which is rejected becomes a cost of undertaking the preferred course of action”.

  6. 6.

    Suppose that the increment of wealth is $200,000 and initial wealth is $1,000,000. Although the relative wealth ratios show: \(1,200,000/1,000,000 = 1.2/1\) > \(1,400,000/1,200,000 = 1.167/1,\) people may feel equally happy because relative to people’s income, $200,000 is a huge amount of money which can be used to buy many pricy commodities.

  7. 7.

    This result refutes Kahneman and Tversky’s (1979) claim that “… utility theory. In that theory, for example, the same utility is assigned to a wealth of $100,000, regardless of whether it was reached from a prior wealth of $95,000 or $105,000. Consequently, the choice between a total wealth of $100,000 and even chances to own $95,000 or $105,000 should be independent of whether one currently owns the smaller or the larger of these two amounts” (p. 273).

  8. 8.

    Thaler (1980, p. 50) argues that this is the Weber-Frechner law: the just noticeable difference in any stimulus is proportional to the stimulus. However, this law is an application of relative price ratio in decision-making.

  9. 9.

    See also Thaler (1980, p. 50).

  10. 10.

    In Kahneman et al. (1979), 3,000 is the median net monthly income for a family in Israel currency (p. 264).

  11. 11.

    This experiment was done at Xi’an Jiao Tong University in 2018. The number of the subjects (most are undergraduates) is 158. CNY3,000 is about the median monthly income of a new college graduate. CNY3 is the price of a lottery. The author wishes to thank Professor Qin, Botao for his help in designing this experiment.

  12. 12.

    Thaler and Johnson’s (1990) experiment find that a large majority of subjects prefer temporal separation of gains to have them occur together. They also find that most subjects prefer temporal separation of losses to have them occur together. I think this may due to the fact that large sum of loss could seriously affect people’s consumption levels (life style). People will prefer to amortize the loss to separate periods (as companies always do to avoid a big drop in their stock prices).

  13. 13.

    Microeconomics states that if a good is a normal good and hence a non-Giffen good, then WTA is greater than WTP. When there is no income effect, WTA and WTP are equal.

  14. 14.

    Barberis (2013) suggests that “upon receiving a negative income shock, the individual prefers to lower future consumption rather than current consumption. After all, news that future consumption will be lower than expected is less painful than news that current consumption is lower than expected.” (p. 188). This indicates that people care more about the current consumption level than the future consumption level because lower consumption now is painful, and if people know that the future consumption may be lower, they still have a chance/choice to work hard to fix it.

  15. 15.

    This is not to say that self-control problem, e.g., drug or alcohol addiction, does not exist. DellaVigna, and Malmendier (2006) use a data of three U.S. health club to find that “members who choose a contract with a flat monthly fee of over $70 attend on average fewer than 4.5 times per month. They pay a price per expected visit of more than $17, even though they could pay $10 per visit using a ten-visit pass. On average, these users forego savings of over $600 during their membership” (p. 716). This shows that people feel they will use the gym more than seven times a month, and hence, choose to pay $70 a month. However, later on, people may choose other activities which give them higher utilities.

  16. 16.

    Let the initial wealth be \(x\) where \(x > \$ 2000\). Then \(\left( {x + \$ 2,000} \right)/x - x/\left( {x - \$ 2,000} \right) = - \$ 4,000,000/\left[ {x\left( {x - \$ 2,000} \right)} \right] < 0\).

  17. 17.

    The existence of a real-valued utility function requires three assumptions: (i) Completeness: for any two alternatives bundles A and B, at least one of three conditions exists: \({\text{A}}\underset{\raise0.3em\hbox{$\smash{\scriptscriptstyle\thicksim}$}}{ \succ } {\text{B}}\), \({\text{B}}\underset{\raise0.3em\hbox{$\smash{\scriptscriptstyle\thicksim}$}}{ \succ } {\text{A}}\) or \({\text{A}}\sim {\text{B}}\) (where \(\tilde{ \succ }\) denotes “at least as good as …..”, and \(\sim\) denotes “indifferent to”); (ii) Transitivity: for any three alternatives A, B and C, if \({\text{A}}\underset{\raise0.3em\hbox{$\smash{\scriptscriptstyle\thicksim}$}}{ \succ } {\text{B}}\) and \({\text{B}}\underset{\raise0.3em\hbox{$\smash{\scriptscriptstyle\thicksim}$}}{ \succ } {\text{C}}\), then \({\text{A}}\underset{\raise0.3em\hbox{$\smash{\scriptscriptstyle\thicksim}$}}{ \succ } {\text{C}}\); (iii) Continuous Preference: for any \(x\) and \(z\) consumption bundles, if \(x \succ z\), then for any alternative \(y\) which is very close to\(x\), we still have\(y \succ z\). The first and second assumptions are also called ‘rational preference’ which are the features of the real number system \({\mathbb{R}}\).

  18. 18.

    Samuelson, Paul (1963) Risk and uncertainty: a fallacy of large numbers. Scientia 98: 108–13.

  19. 19.

    Rabin, Matthew and Richard Thaler (2001) Anomalies: risk Aversion. Journal of Economic Perspectives 15: 219-232.

  20. 20.

    Also, it won’t be easy for a very high-income person to voluntarily pay a tithe.

  21. 21.

    Some scholars claim that investors may have the so-called narrow framing bias, i.e., investors make investment decisions without considering the context of their entire portfolio. However, using portfolio to diversify cannot create or add value i.e., financial diversification irrelevancy. Also, since stocks and house are the main part of a household’s wealth, investors of course will pay much more attention to these two assets.

  22. 22.

    Benartzi, Shlomo and Richard Thaler (1995) Myopic loss aversion and the equity premium puzzle. Quarterly Journal of Economics 110: 73–92.

  23. 23.

    Siegel (1992) The Equity premium: stock and bond returns since 1802. Financial Analysts Journal 48: 28–38.

  24. 24.

    There are some other biases which may be related to transaction costs. (1) Herd behavior: people do what others are doing instead of using their own information or making independent decisions. Investors may believe others have already done enough research and imitate their actions. (2) Home bias: individuals and institutions in most countries hold only modest amounts of foreign equity, and tend to strongly favor company stock from their home nation. This may be the result of the extra difficulties associated with investing in foreign equities, such as legal restrictions and additional transaction costs. (3) Overconfidence: people’s tendency to overestimate their abilities to make very risky investments. Probably, all start-ups and entrepreneurs have the overconfidence feature to innovate. (4) People rely too much on extrapolation of recent trends. Recent information may signal the beginning of a different path. People will regret if they miss this information/signal. (5) Affect: investors and consumers may feel good about a company that has a good reputation of corporate social responsibility. Good reputation may save the search cost of finding a good investment or product. (6) Equity carve-outs. For example, company A has sold a stake of a subsidiary (company B) to the public and has announced its intention to spin off the remaining shares in company B at some point in the not-too-distant future. However, the market value of A is found lower than the value of the shares of B that it owns. This is an example of limits to arbitrage: the difficulty of short-selling the overpriced carveout shares.

  25. 25.

    Shefrin, Hersh and Meir Statman (1985) The disposition to sell winners too early and ride losers too long: Theory and evidence. Journal of Finance 40: 777–790.

  26. 26.

    Odean, Terrance (1998) Are investors reluctant to realize their losses? Journal of Finance 53: 1775–1798.

  27. 27.

    Mankiw, Gregory and Stephen Zeldes (1991), “The consumption of stockholders and nonstockholders,” Journal of Financial Economics 29: 97–111.

References

  • Akerlof, G. (1991). Procrastination and obedience. American Economic Review, 81, 1–19.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arkes, H., & Blumer, C. (1985). The psychology of sunk cost. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 35, 124–140.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ashraf, N., Berry, J., & Shapiro, J. (2010). Can higher prices stimulate product use? evidence from a field experiment in Zambia. American Economic Review, 100, 2383–2413.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barberis, N. (2013). Thirty years of prospect theory in economics: A review and assessment. Journal of Economic Perspectives, 27, 173–195.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brockner, J., Shaw, M., & Rubin, J. (1979). Factors affecting withdrawal from an escalating conflict: Quitting before it’s too late. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 15, 492–503.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, J. (1969). Cost and choice: An inquiry in economic theory. The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, J. (2008) Opportunity cost. In New Palgrave dictionary of economics, 2nd ed., eds. by S. N. Durlauf, L. E. Blume. Palgrave Macmillan, New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Camerer, C., Babcock, L., Loewenstein, G., & Thaler, R. (1997). Labor supply of New York city cabdrivers: One day at a time. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 112, 407–441.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chang, K.-P. (2015). The ownership of the firm, corporate finance, and derivatives: Some critical thinking. Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Chang, K.-P. (2005) Prospect theory or a misuse of the concept of opportunity cost? http://ssrn.com/abstract=687704.

  • Chang, K.-P. (2018) On using risk-neutral probabilities to price assets. http://ssrn.com/abstract=3114126.

  • Chang, K.-P. (2019) Behavioral economics versus traditional economics: are they very different? http://ssrn.com/abstract=3350088.

  • Cohen, D., & Knetsch, J. (1992). Judicial choice and disparities between measures of economic values. Osgoode Hall Law Journal, 30, 737–770.

    Google Scholar 

  • Daniel, K., Knetsch, J., & Thaler, R. (1990). Experimental tests of the endowment effect and the Coase theorem. Journal of Political Economy, 98, 1325–1348.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • DellaVigna, S., & Malmendier, U. (2006). Paying not to go to the gym. American Economic Review, 96, 694–719.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ferraro, P., Laura, T. (2005) Do economists recognize an opportunity cost when they see one? a dismal performance from the dismal science. The B.E. Journal of Economic Analysis & Policy, 4, 1–14.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frank, R., & Bernanke, B. (2001). Principles of microeconomics. McGraw-Hill/Irwin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, M., & Savage, L. (1948). The utility analysis of choices involving risk. Journal of Political Economy, 56, 279–304.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, D., Pommerenke, K., Lukose, R., Milam, G., & Huberman, B. (2007). Searching for the sunk cost fallacy. Experimental Economics, 10, 79–104.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gourville, J., & Soman, D. (1998). Payment depreciation: The behavioral effects of temporarily separating payments from consumption. Journal of Consumer Research, 25, 160–174.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Just, D., & Wansink, B. (2011). The flat-rate pricing paradox: Conflicting effects of all-you-can-eat buffet pricing. Review of Economics and Statistics, 93, 193–200.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, D. (2011). Thinking, fast and slow. Farrar.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, D., & Tversky, A. (1979). Prospect theory: An analysis of decision under risk. Econometrica, 47, 263–291.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, D., & Tversky, A. (1984). Choices, values, and frames. The American Psychologist, 39, 341–350.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Knetsch, J., & Sinden, J. A. (1984). Willingness to pay and compensation demanded: Experimental evidence of an unexpected disparity in measures of value. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 99, 507–521.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Michael, H. (1991). Willingness to pay and willingness to accept: How much can they differ? American Economic Review, 81, 635–647.

    Google Scholar 

  • Northcraft, G., & Wolf, G. (1984). Dollars, sense, and sunk costs: A life-cycle model of resource allocation decisions. Academy of Management Review, 9, 225–234.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shafir, E., & Thaler, R. (2006). Invest now, drink later, spend never: On the mental accounting of delayed consumption. Journal of Economic Psychology, 27, 694–712.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sussman, A. B., & Shafir, E. (2012). On assets and debt in the psychology of perceived wealth. Psychological Science, 23, 101–108.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thaler, R. (1980). Toward a positive theory of consumer choice. Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, 1, 39–60.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thaler, R. (2018). From cashews to nudges: The evolution of behavioral economics. American Economic Review, 108, 1265–1287.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thaler, R., & Johnson, E. (1990). Gambling with the house money and trying to break even: The effects of prior outcomes on risky choice. Management Science, 36, 643–660.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thirlby, G. F. (1946). The ruler. South African Journal of Economics, 14, 253–276.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tversky, A., Kahneman, D. (1986). Rational choice and the framing of decisions. Journal of Business, 59(4), part 2: The behavioral foundations of economic theory, S251–S278.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tversky, A., & Kahneman, D. (1981). The framing of decisions and the rationality of choice. Science, 211, 453–458.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tversky, A., & Kahneman, D. (1992). Advances in prospect theory: Cumulative representation of uncertainty. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 5, 297–323.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zhang, Y., & Sussman, A. (2018). Perspectives on mental accounting: An exploration of budgeting and investing. Financial Planning Review, 2018(1), e1011. https://doi.org/10.1002/cfp2.1011

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Kuo-Ping Chang .

Appendices

Appendix A: Opportunity Cost in Practice

The following is a true story from Chang (2005). One day a senior student (Jade) came to my office, and told me happily that she just got admitted to a prestigious university to pursue her master degree in finance.

Jade: Professor, I am so happy that I got admitted to X university.

Professor: Congratulations! ... But did you also apply for other disciplines, such as MS or Ph.D. programs in computer science, statistics, or economics?

Jade: No. Why should I? If I pursue these degrees, then my past four-year study of finance would be a waste.

Professor: Apparently, you do not understand the meaning of opportunity cost. Your study of Principles of Economics (Econ101) and Financial Management (Fin101) courses is a waste and futile.

Jade: I don’t quite follow you. Could you explain it to me?

Professor: Let me give you an example. A beautiful girl who just enrolls in a university meets a boy. When the boy asks her to go on a date, she agrees. Two weeks later, the boy asks for more dating, and the girl contemplates: “If I stop dating him, then my two weeks of dating (investment) will be a waste.” Hence, they continue to date for another two years. After two years, the girl contemplates again: “If I stop dating him, then my previous two years of dating him will be a waste.” They continue to date for two more years. After four years, upon graduation, the boy asks the girl to marry him. The girl contemplates: “If I do not marry him, then my four years of dating him will go to waste,” and so she marries the boy. You are that girl.

Jade: No, I’m not. I am not that stupid!

Professor: Oh, yes, you are. If you are this discreet with your marriage, then be even more so in choosing your profession.

What matters in Jade’s choosing a particular graduate program is: Does it provide positive net present value (NPV, the difference between revenues and costs), and is its NPV the largest one among all the mutually exclusive projects (graduate programs)? Costs in the NPV analysis are opportunity costs, which means that you still have the opportunity to make the choice to spend or not to spend, i.e., opportunity costs are ex-ante (Buchanan, 1969). When calculating the NPV of joining a finance graduate program, Jade should consider only how much more costs and time she will spend, and compare them with the revenues (cash flows) she will receive if she finishes the study. Jade’s four-year study of finance is already sunk; it is not an opportunity cost, and therefore should not be considered in decision-making.

Appendix B: Expected Utility Theory and Risky Assets

Example A.1

A consumer decides to buy \(\alpha\) units of insurance. When there is an event, every unit of insurance bought will pay one dollar. One unit of insurance costs \(q\) dollars (where \(q < 1\)). Suppose the consumer’s wealth is \(w\), the probability of event is \(\pi\), and total loss will be \(D\) dollars. The consumer has a strictly concave utility function: \(u^{\prime}\left( w \right) > 0\;,\;u^{\prime\prime}\left( w \right) < 0\), and is using the expected utility function to make decision:

$$ \mathop {Max}\limits_{\alpha \ge 0} \;\;{ }U = \left( {1 - \pi } \right) \cdot u\left( {w - \alpha q} \right) + \pi \cdot u\left( {w - \alpha q - D + \alpha \cdot 1} \right) $$
(A.1)

or

$$ \begin{gathered} \mathop {Max}\limits_{\alpha ,s} \;\;{ }U = \left( {1 - \pi } \right) \cdot u\left( {w - \alpha q} \right) + \pi \cdot u\left( {w - \alpha q - D + \alpha } \right) \hfill \\ s.t.\quad { } - \alpha + s^{2} = 0 \hfill \\ \end{gathered} $$

By the Lagrangian method:

$$ \mathop {Max}\limits_{\alpha ,\lambda ,s} \;\;{ }L = \left( {1 - \pi } \right) \cdot u\left( {w - \alpha q} \right) + \pi \cdot u\left( {w - \alpha q - D + \alpha } \right) - \lambda \left[ { - \alpha + s^{2} } \right] $$
(A.2)

Since \(u\left( \cdot \right)\) is strictly concave, and hence, the expected utility function is also strictly concave. The first-order condition of Eq. (A.2) is both necessary and sufficient conditions:

1st-order condition:

$$ \begin{aligned} & \frac{\partial L}{{\partial \alpha }} = \left( {1 - \pi } \right) \cdot u^{\prime}\left( {w - \alpha q} \right)\left( { - q} \right) + \pi \cdot u^{\prime}\left( {w - D + \alpha \left( {1 - q} \right)} \right) \cdot \left( {1 - q} \right) + \lambda \equiv 0 \\ & \frac{\partial L}{{\partial \lambda }} = - \left[ { - \alpha + s^{2} } \right] \equiv 0 \\ & \frac{\partial L}{{\partial s}} = - 2\lambda s \equiv 0 \\ \end{aligned} $$

Its Kuhn-Tucker condition is:

$$ \left\{ \begin{aligned} & \left( {\text{I}} \right)\quad \left( {1 - \pi } \right) \cdot u^{\prime}\left( {w - \alpha^{*} q} \right)\left( { - q} \right) + \pi \cdot u^{\prime}\left( {w - D + \alpha^{*} \left( {1 - q} \right)} \right) \cdot \left( {1 - q} \right) \le 0 \\ & \left( {{\text{II}}} \right)\;\;\left[ {\left( {1 - \pi } \right) \cdot u^{\prime}\left( {w - \alpha^{*} q} \right)\left( { - q} \right) + \pi \cdot u^{\prime}\left( {w - D + \alpha^{*} \left( {1 - q} \right)} \right) \cdot \left( {1 - q} \right)} \right] \cdot \alpha^{*} = 0 \\ & \left( {{\text{III}}} \right)\; \alpha^{*} \ge 0,\lambda^{*} \ge 0 \\ \end{aligned} \right. $$
(A.3)

Assume that the insurance company is risk-neutral (i.e., it treats expected value as certain value) and earns no excess profits:

$$ q - \left[ {\pi \cdot 1 + \left( {1 - \pi } \right) \cdot 0} \right] = 0 \Rightarrow q = \pi $$

Hence, Eq. (A.3)’s (I) and (II) become:

$$ \left\{ {\left( {\text{I}} \right)\quad u^{\prime}\left( {w - D + \alpha^{*} \left( {1 - \pi } \right)} \right) - u^{\prime}\left( {w - \alpha^{*} \pi } \right) \le 0} \right. $$
(A.4a)
$$ \left\{ {\left( {{\text{II}}} \right)\;\;\left[ {u^{\prime}\left( {w - D + \alpha^{*} \left( {1 - \pi } \right)} \right) - u^{\prime}\left( {w - \alpha^{*} \pi } \right)} \right] \cdot \alpha^{*} = 0} \right. $$
(A.4b)

If in Eq. (A.4a), \(u^{\prime}\left( {w - D + \alpha^{*} \left( {1 - \pi } \right)} \right) - u^{\prime}\left( {w - \alpha^{*} \pi } \right) < 0\), then from Eq. (A.4b) we get: \(\alpha^{*} = 0\). But because of \(u^{\prime}\left( \cdot \right) > 0\) and \(u^{\prime\prime}\left( \cdot \right) < 0\), there will be a contradiction:

\(\begin{aligned}u^{\prime}\left( {w - D + \alpha^{*} \left( {1 - \pi } \right)} \right) - u^{\prime}\left( {w - \alpha^{*} \pi } \right)\langle {0 \Rightarrow w - D + \alpha^{*} \left( {1 - \pi } \right)} \rangle w - \alpha^{*} \pi \\ \Rightarrow \alpha^{*} > D. \\ \end{aligned}\)

It is impossible to have \(\alpha^{*} > D\). Therefore, from equation (A.4a), we know that \(u^{\prime}\left( {w - D + \alpha^{*} \left( {1 - \pi } \right)} \right) - u^{\prime}\left( {w - \alpha^{*} \pi } \right)\) must be equal to zero. Also, because \(u\left( w \right)\) is monotonically increasing in \(w\), we have:

$$ \begin{aligned} u^{\prime } \left( {w - D + \alpha ^{*} \left( {1 - \pi } \right)} \right) - u^{\prime } \left( {w - \alpha ^{*} \pi } \right) & = 0 \Rightarrow w - D + \alpha ^{*} \left( {1 - \pi } \right) \\ & = w - \alpha ^{*} \pi \Rightarrow \alpha ^{*} = D. \\ \end{aligned} $$

That is, this consumer will buy 100% insurance. However, to prevent the moral hazard problem (i.e., the insured may handle her asset carelessly), the insurance company may not sell 100% insurance. But according to the endowment effect, the insurance company will sell 100% insurance because the insured feels attached to her asset.

Example A.2

Assume a one-period model, and there are two kinds of assets: one gives certain outcome (one dollar for one dollar), another gives uncertain payoff z where \(\smallint zdF\left( z \right) > 1\), \(F\left( z \right)\) is the cumulative distribution of \(z\). At the beginning of the period, the consumer will allocate her wealth \(w\) to the two assets: \(w = \alpha + \beta\). At the end of the period, she will get wealth: \(\alpha \cdot 1 + \beta \cdot z\). Suppose that her utility function is strictly concave: \(u^{\prime}\left( w \right) > 0\) and \(u^{\prime\prime}\left( w \right) < 0\), and she makes decision based on the expected utility function:

$$ \mathop {Max}\limits_{\alpha ,\beta \ge 0} \;\;{ }U = \smallint u\left( {\alpha + \beta z} \right)dF\left( z \right) $$
$$ s.t.\quad { }w = \alpha + \beta $$
(A.5)

Substitute \(\alpha = w - \beta\) into the objective function:

$$ \mathop {Max}\limits_{\beta } \;\;{ }U = \smallint u\left( {w + \beta \left( {z - 1} \right)} \right)dF\left( z \right) $$
$$ s.t.\quad { }0 \le \beta \le w\;,\quad {\text{or}}\quad \left\{ {\begin{array}{*{20}c} {\beta \ge 0 \Rightarrow - \beta + s_{1}^{2} = 0\quad } \\ {\beta \le w \Rightarrow \beta - w + s_{2}^{2} = 0} \\ \end{array} } \right. $$

By the Lagrangian method:

$$ \mathop {Max}\limits_{{\begin{array}{*{20}c} {\beta ,\lambda_{1} ,s_{1} ,} \\ {\lambda_{2} ,s_{2} } \\ \; \\ \end{array} }} \quad L = \smallint u\left( {w + \beta \left( {z - 1} \right)} \right)dF\left( z \right) - \lambda_{1} \left[ { - \beta + s_{1}^{2} } \right] - \lambda_{2} \left[ {\beta - w + s_{2}^{2} } \right] $$

1st-order condition:

$$ \begin{aligned} & \frac{\partial L}{{\partial \beta }} = \smallint u^{\prime}\left( {w + \beta \left( {z - 1} \right)} \right)\left( {z - 1} \right)dF\left( z \right) + \lambda_{1} - \lambda_{2} \equiv 0 \\ & \frac{\partial L}{{\partial \lambda_{1} }} = - \left[ { - \beta + s_{1}^{2} } \right] \equiv 0 \\ & \frac{\partial L}{{\partial s_{1} }} = - 2\lambda_{1} s_{1} \equiv 0 \\ & \frac{\partial L}{{\partial \lambda_{2} }} = - \left[ {\beta - w + s_{2}^{2} } \right] \equiv 0 \\ & \frac{\partial L}{{\partial s_{2} }} = - 2\lambda_{2} s_{2} \equiv 0 \\ \end{aligned} $$

Its Kuhn-Tucker condition is:

$$ \left\{ \begin{aligned} & \left( {\text{I}} \right)\quad \smallint u^{\prime}\left( {w + \beta^{*} \left( {z - 1} \right)} \right)\left( {z - 1} \right)dF\left( z \right) = \lambda_{2}^{*} - \lambda_{1}^{*} \\ & \left( {{\text{II}}} \right)\;\; \lambda_{1}^{*} \cdot \beta^{*} = 0 \\ & \left( {{\text{III}}} \right)\; \lambda_{2}^{*} \cdot \left( {\beta^{*} - w} \right) = 0 \\ & \left( {{\text{IV}}} \right)\;{ }w \ge \beta^{*} \ge 0; \lambda_{1}^{*} ,\lambda_{2}^{*} \ge 0 \\ \end{aligned} \right. $$
(A.6)

From the first-order condition and Eq. (A.6):

$$ \begin{gathered} {\text{If}}\quad s_{2}^{*} \ne 0\quad ({\text{i}}.{\text{e}}.,\quad 0 \le \beta ^{*} < w),\;{\text{then}}\;\lambda _{2}^{*} = 0\;{\text{and}}\; \hfill \\ \int {u^{\prime } \left( {w + \beta ^{*} \left( {z - 1} \right)} \right)\left( {z - 1} \right)dF\left( z \right) = - \lambda _{1}^{*} \le 0} \hfill \\ \end{gathered} $$
(A.6a)
$$ \begin{gathered} {\text{If}}\quad s_{1}^{*} \ne 0\quad ({\text{i}}.{\text{e}}.,\quad \beta ^{*} > 0),\;{\text{then}}\;\lambda _{1}^{*} = 0\;{\text{and}}\; \hfill \\ \int {u^{\prime } \left( {w + \beta ^{*} \left( {z - 1} \right)} \right)\left( {z - 1} \right)dF\left( z \right) = \lambda _{2}^{*} \ge 0} \hfill \\ \end{gathered} $$
(A.6b)

If in Eq. (A.6a), \(\beta^{*} = 0\), then because \(u^{\prime}\left( w \right) > 0\) and \(\smallint \left( {z - 1} \right)dF\left( z \right) > 0\),

$$ [\smallint u^{\prime}\left( {w + \beta^{*} \left( {z - 1} \right)} \right) \cdot \left( {z - 1} \right)dF\left( z \right)]_{{\beta^{*} = 0}} = u^{\prime}\left( w \right)\smallint \left( {z - 1} \right)dF\left( z \right) > 0 $$

which contradicts Eq. (A.6a). Thus, we must have \(0 < \beta^{*} < w\), i.e., the consumer’s investment portfolio must contain some risky assets.

Problems

  1. 1.

    Suppose you're on a game show, and you're given the choice of three doors: Behind one door is $1,000,000; behind the others, $0. You choose a door, say No. 1, and the host, who knows what's behind the doors, opens another door, say No. 3, which has $0. He then says to you, “Do you want to choose door No. 2?”

Questions

  1. (1)

    How many choices do you have in this game?

  2. (2)

    If the host opens two other doors, how many choices do you have in this game?

  3. (3)

    If the host opens no door and asks you to choose again, how many choices do you have in this game?

  1. 2.

    Suppose that an individual is offered a bet: ($100,000, 0.50; $50,000, 0.50). Mankiw and Zeldes (1991) argue that a person with a coefficient of relative risk aversion of 30 would be indifferent between this gamble and a certain consumption of $51,209. Give your comments on this claim.Footnote 27

  2. 3.

    Some researchers claim that most common errors among individuals are: under-diversification, holding onto losers, chasing winners, buying stocks that catch their attention, systematically ignoring important information, paying too little attention to fees and trading too much. What do you think?

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2023 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Singapore Pte Ltd.

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Chang, KP. (2023). Behavioral Finance and Corporate Finance. In: Corporate Finance: A Systematic Approach. Springer Texts in Business and Economics. Springer, Singapore. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-981-19-9119-6_11

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics