Skip to main content

The Nature of the Public-Owned Enterprise

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Property Rights and Changes in China
  • 165 Accesses

Abstract

This paper studies the nature of two types of public-owned enterprises (POEs): state-owned enterprises (SOEs) and collective-owned enterprises (COEs). Generally speaking, a POE is either as “an enterprise distinctly belonged to the state or the collective”, or an “ownerless property” and an organization with absent owners.

This paper was originally published in Economic Review, Issue No. 11 (2000).

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    See the introductory part of Barzel (1989), and also the Preface by Wang (1998), for the Chinese version of A Collection of Barzel’s Papers (1989).

  2. 2.

    The Theory of Rent Dissipation by Cheung (1970) argues that if public resources do not go against being used by free competition, it will definitely cause rent dissipation. However, here the foundation for anyone to use public resources through competition is not the private right as defined by law over the assembled property, but rather the “de facto right” as discussed in later sections. Fan and Zhang (1990: 25) propose that “the labor is not the owner of public property”; Rong (1996: 18) points out that public property “has a unique internal exclusivity”, namely the exclusive right of the collective will to go against the will of the individual, who is required by the public ownership not to steal, damage, abuse, or waste public property. Their common focus is on the provision of rights of public ownership in the sense of legal power.

  3. 3.

    The property rights include the right to trade, that is, the right to enter into a market contract. The exclusivity of property rights is important, but it is mainly for trade, not just for exclusive self-use.

  4. 4.

    The idea that a firm is a series of market contracts makes the statement of “the ownership of the firm” a paradox because it takes the ownership of at least two or more resources to form a firm, so “the corporate contract”, just like “a tenancy contract”, cannot only belong to either one of the contracting parties; and the market value of the same contract is different for different parties (Zhou 1996: 76). The non-contract-based POE that announces elimination of private ownership of the means of production seems to have only one ownership because all resources are owned by the public, so there is no second ownership. However, the main purpose of this paper is to show that this is only true in the sense of legal power.

  5. 5.

    Cheung (1983: 3).

  6. 6.

    Coase (1937: 6).

  7. 7.

    Coase (1937: 5).

  8. 8.

    The role of entrepreneurship is difficult to monitor and measure even afterwards. Except such institutional arrangements as a sharecropping contract, where the entrepreneur is allowed to share the residual claims, probably nothing else could “incentivize” entrepreneurs. (Zhou 1996: 76).

  9. 9.

    The selection of qualified entrepreneurs or company managers is important, but the effectiveness of such selection is inseparable from the overall market environment. As for the theory of Zhang (1995) that the financial capital owner of the firm should have the priority to choose the manager, this priority can only be correctly interpreted when it is placed in the market environment, especially in the markets of various factors. The shareholders and BOD usually select the GM once a year, but workers, technicians, and other input owners who enter into the firm can select their managers every day, and they can even select the “company boss” who chooses managers. They can withdraw from the firm at a certain exit cost, or stay in the firm to create trouble for their boss. Whether the financial capital owner will choose managers from the “leftovers” from other inputs owners depends on whether these “bosses” meet economists’ assumption that they are always rational. In the real empirical world, there are stories and stories of “bosses” destroying their financial capital to zero with their stubbornness, capriciousness, arrogance and dictatorship. We only assume that all “bosses surviving bosses are rational” when the competitive market will eventually oust all bosses who fail the survival test. In theory, I think Cui Zhiyuan’s “stakeholders” concept (1996) is meaningful for understanding Coase’s concept of “the firm as a set of market contracts”. But I just disagree with Cui on his argument that to acknowledge that company manager is responsible to all stakeholders is to “transcend the logic of private property rights”, because the foundation for stakeholders to enter the company as a contract is that they have the property rights over their respective resources (including human capital).

  10. 10.

    However, Cheung’s interpretation of Coase’s theory of the firm is often summarized in much of the literature as “the firm is organization that replaces the products market by the factors market”. The reason for the firm to exist is to use input contracts to get the right to use the resources through the owner’s alienation, while the owner could otherwise use the resources to produce products and sell them. However, the firm, as a profit-making organization as described by Coase, cannot replace any market, including the product market. If the product market is truly completely replaced, then the resource owner can no longer choose to be an entrepreneur to make the product in the market, he has no choice but to transfer the right to use the resource to other entrepreneurs, and then how to guarantee that this enterprise (of other entrepreneurs) will have a real competitive edge?

  11. 11.

    For the evolution of economics thoughts about the role of knowledge and other forms of human capital in economic growth, see Wang (1995). The author would like to thank Wang Dingding for his comments on the draft of this article, especially for his insight that “learning” is the most important component of human capital.

  12. 12.

    Zhou (1996: 73–74).

  13. 13.

    Zhang (1996) believes that the feature that “human capital is indivisible from the person” puts human capital at a disadvantage as compared with non-human capital: first, human capital cannot be mortgaged; second, human capital owners can get benefits by “slacking off” and “abusing” non-human capital. Therefore, he believes that the correct logical inference is “capital hires labor”, and he believes that “(non-human) capital owners should be given the precedence to be entrepreneurs” (Zhang 1996: 9–10). I believe if “reputation” is regarded as an intangible part of the human asset, then the statement “human capital cannot be mortgaged” is not necessarily true, because it would be rather too difficult to interpret modern companies if we throw away the market mechanism to price the reputation and only rely on the mortgageable financial capital. As for the tendency of “slacking off” and “abusing”, it seems to me that the problem cannot be solved by giving the non-human capital the priority to be the entrepreneur, for the same reason as Barzel (1977) points out the slave owner with the absolute priority cannot solve the problem of “slacking off” and “abusing” by slaves. The effective way to solve the problem is the market contract with incentives, rather than establishing the precedence of “capital” over “labor.”

  14. 14.

    Many economists advocating the POE reform propose that the introduction of the “profit” into the POE system can help the POE to increase productivity. In 1962, the famous “Liberman’s proposal” of the Soviet Union advocated highly simplifying the state plan for business indicators, and using the “profit” (uniformly approved sectoral profit level) as the main indicator for assessing enterprises. In the 1960s, Sun Yefang of China also made a similar proposal (see Wu 1994: 122–129). However, “profit” is the product of enterprise contract in the market transactions. When the POE system abolishes the market transaction, the so-called “profit” that is “uniformly approved” and directed by the central planning is not the “profit” in its original sense. In contrast, Gu Zhun’s proposal is not so compromised. He believes that “the mandatory plan and mandatory pricing system must be abolished to liberalize prices” in order to guide enterprises towards making profits” (see Wu 1994: 127).

  15. 15.

    This is the fundamental reason why the decisions on the growth targets, speed, priority sectors, and even key projects under the planned economy are often full of political struggle.

  16. 16.

    See Wang Dingding’s systematic interpretation of Hayek’s thought (1995, 1999).

  17. 17.

    In theory, the value of pensions and other funds appropriated from POEs can achieve value addition through investment into productive assets such that the individuals no longer need to worry about themselves in case of loss of productivity. However, the pooled funds are like another type of public passage. There must be incentives to ensure that these funds are well managed. Otherwise, they could as well be drained and depleted due to mismanagement. Empirically, if POEs cannot fulfill their welfare commitments, it will cause serious social unrest, and it may lead to the so-called “59-year-old phenomenon” (The phenomenon refers to graft and corruption of officials bordering retirement—Translator’s note).

References

  • Alchian, A. (1950). Uncertainty, Evolution, and Economic Theory. Journal of Political Economy, 58(3), 211–221.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alchian, A., and Harold Demsetz. 1972. Production, Information Costs, and Economic Organization. American Economic Review 62: 777–795.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barzel, Yoram. 1977. An Economic Analysis of Slavery. Journal of Law and Economics 17 (I): 73–96.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barzel, Yoram. 1989. Economic Analysis of Property Rights. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barzel, Yoram. 1992. The Property Rights of Public Property. In The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics. Economic Science Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cheung, Steven. 1983. The Contractual Nature of the Firm. Journal of Law and Economics, 26 (1), 1–21.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cheung, Steven, N.S. 1970. The Structure of a Contract and the Theory of a Non-Exclusive Resource. The Journal of Law and Economics 13 (1): 47–70.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cheung, Steven, N.S. 1984. The Orange Seller’s Words. Hong Kong Economic Journal.

    Google Scholar 

  • Coase, Ronald. 1937. The Nature of the Firm. In The Firm, the Market, and the Law, ed. Coase, 1988. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cui, Zhiyuan. 1996. The Theoretical Background for Amendments to Corporate Law in 29 States of the United States. Economic Research (4): 35–40.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fan, Gang, Shuguang Zhang, et al. 1990. The Outline of Macroeconomic Theory of Public Ownership. Shanghai Joint Publishing Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hayek, F.A. 1945. The Use of Knowledge in Society. American Economic Review (September).

    Google Scholar 

  • Knight, Frank. 1921. Risk, Uncertainty, and Profit. Reprints of Economic Classics. Angustus M. Kelley, 1964.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rong, Zhaozhi. 1996. On Inherent Conflicts in Public Property Rights. Economic Research (9): 16–23.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosen, S. 1985. The Theory of Equalizing Differences. In Handbook of Labour Economics, ed. O. Ashenfelter and R. Layard. Amsterdam: North-Holland.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wang, Dingding. 1995. Economic Development and Institutional Innovation. Shanghai People’s Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wang, Dingding. 1996. The Gaming of Property Rights. Economic Research (10): 70–80.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wang, Dingding. 1998. Foreword to Chinese Translation. In Property Rights Economics Analysis. Shanghai Joint Publishing Press and Shanghai People’s Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wang, Dingding. 1999. Study on Hayek’s ‘Extended Order’. In Towards a Clearing in the Forest (WANG Dingding’s Anthology). Shandong Education Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wu, Jinglian. 1994. Modern Companies and Enterprise Reform. Tianjin People’s Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zhang, Weiying. 1995. The Entrepreneur’s Enterprise: The Contract Theory. Shanghai Joint Publishing Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zhang, Weiying. 1996. Ownership, Governance Structure and Principal-Agent Relationship. Economic Research (9): 3–15.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zhou, Qiren. 1996. The Enterprise in the Market: A Special Contract Between Human Capital and Non-Human Capital. Economic Research (6): 71–80.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Qiren Zhou .

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2020 Peking University Press and Springer Nature Singapore Pte Ltd.

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Zhou, Q. (2020). The Nature of the Public-Owned Enterprise. In: Property Rights and Changes in China. Springer, Singapore. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-981-15-9885-2_8

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-981-15-9885-2_8

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Singapore

  • Print ISBN: 978-981-15-9884-5

  • Online ISBN: 978-981-15-9885-2

  • eBook Packages: Economics and FinanceEconomics and Finance (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics