Skip to main content

Knowing as Simply Being Correct

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Facts and Evidence
  • 229 Accesses

Abstract

Western epistemologists have long told us a simple tale of how we must begin to conceive of knowledge’s nature. But they have long been on conceptually weaker ground than they have assumed is so. This paper will tell an alternative story about that same phenomenon.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 139.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 179.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 179.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    The translation here is from Grube (1981).

  2. 2.

    As I indicated, epistemologists have standardly interpreted Socrates’ talk of an account of “the reason why” in terms of the possession of evidence. However, spurred on especially by Goldman (1979, 1986), many contemporary epistemologists eschew any commitment to knowledge’s needing to include evidence. That commitment is deemed to be epistemically internalist; and those epistemologists are content instead with an externalist substitute, such as your forming the belief in a way that is generally reliable as a way of forming true beliefs. That externalist approach can also be extended, from talking about your forming the belief, to explicating your maintaining the belief. Above, I have parsed Socrates as requiring the evidence to accompany the correct opinion. Below, we will focus on whether that could be enough—or whether instead something more active is needed-in what we say about evidence’s role within knowing.

  3. 3.

    I say “caution” because a stronger version of this conception might instead be thought to emerge no less clearly from Socrates’ argument in the Meno. On that stronger version, we do not say merely that knowledge is at least a justified true belief; we say that it is a justified true belief—that knowledge is nothing less than, but also nothing more than, a justified true belief. More strongly still, we would say that this is how knowledge is to be defined. Of course, that stronger account was famously challenged by Edmund Gettier (1963), when—with two hypothesized situations—he questioned the sufficiency of a belief’s being true and justified for its being knowledge. Still, even Gettier did not question the necessity, to a belief’s being knowledge, of its being true and justified. He thus left intact the “at least” in the At Least Justified True Belief conception, and it is that weaker conception upon which we will focus in this paper. For detailed discussion of Gettier’s challenge and its history within the past fifty-plus years of epistemology, see Hetherington (2016).

  4. 4.

    Variations on the idea have been proposed by Goldman (1999: 23–26), Hetherington (2001: ch. 4, 2011, ch. 4), and Foley (2012). For a version much like this paper’s, see Hetherington (forthcoming).

  5. 5.

    And if instead we accord the term “guess” a psychological reading, whereby it indicates the person’s feeling unconfident as to p, we are also not obliged to view the situation as one in which the person believes that p in the first place.

References

  • Foley, R. 2012. When Is True Belief Knowledge? Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gettier, E.L. 1963. Is Justified True Belief Knowledge? Analysis.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A.I. 1979. What Is Justified Belief? In Justification and Knowledge: New Studies in Epistemology, ed. G.S. Pappas. Dordrecht: D. Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A,I. 1986. Epistemology and Cognition. Cambridge, MA and London: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A.I. 1999. Knowledge in a Social World. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grube, G.M.A. 1981. Plato: Five Dialogues. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hetherington, S. 2001. Good Knowledge, Bad Knowledge: On Two Dogmas of Epistemology. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hetherington, S. 2011. How to Know: A Practicalist Conception of Knowledge. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hetherington, S. 2016. Knowledge and the Gettier Problem. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kornblith, H. 1980. Beyond Foundationalism and the Coherence Theory. The Journal of Philosophy 77: 597–611.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sartwell, C. 1991. Knowledge Is Merely True Belief. American Philosophical Quarterly 28 (2): 157–165.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sartwell, C. 1992. Why Knowledge Is Merely True Belief. The Journal of Philosophy 89 (4): 167–180.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2021 China University of Political Science and Law Press

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Hetherington, S. (2021). Knowing as Simply Being Correct. In: Zhang, B., Tong, S., Cao, J., Fan, C. (eds) Facts and Evidence. Springer, Singapore. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-981-15-9639-1_6

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-981-15-9639-1_6

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Singapore

  • Print ISBN: 978-981-15-9638-4

  • Online ISBN: 978-981-15-9639-1

  • eBook Packages: Law and CriminologyLaw and Criminology (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics