Skip to main content

The Continuity of Davidson’s Thought: Non-reductionism Without Quietism

Part of the Logic in Asia: Studia Logica Library book series (LIAA)

Abstract

This chapter focuses on the continuity of Davidson’s thought. My goal is to show that two commonly held conceptions of Davidson’s philosophy, one to the effect that there is a shift from radical interpretation to triangulation, in particular, a shift from reductionism to non-reductionism, the other to the effect that Davidson’s non-reductionism is incompatible with constructive philosophizing, are in fact misconceptions. I argue that, though Davidson’s account of meaning, being non-reductionist, does not spell out non-circular sufficient conditions for any particular utterances to have the meaning they have, and for someone to have a language and thoughts at all, it is nonetheless non-quietist, for it does give us necessary conditions for these phenomena to occur. These necessary conditions first emerge from Davidson’s reflections on radical interpretation and are further articulated in his writings on triangulation, which also demonstrate that radical interpretation is but an instance of triangulation, since they make clear that successful radical interpretation in effect requires triangulation.

Keywords

  • Davidson
  • Meaning
  • Non-reductionism
  • Quietism
  • Radical interpretation
  • Triangulation

This chapter is in its final form and it is not submitted for publication anywhere else.

This is a preview of subscription content, access via your institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • DOI: 10.1007/978-981-15-7230-2_8
  • Chapter length: 16 pages
  • Instant PDF download
  • Readable on all devices
  • Own it forever
  • Exclusive offer for individuals only
  • Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout
eBook
USD   89.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • ISBN: 978-981-15-7230-2
  • Instant PDF download
  • Readable on all devices
  • Own it forever
  • Exclusive offer for individuals only
  • Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout
Softcover Book
USD   119.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
Hardcover Book
USD   119.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)

Notes

  1. 1.

    As he writes: “meaning, and by its connection with meaning, belief also, are open to public determination. I shall take advantage of this fact…and adopt the stance of a radical interpreter when asking about the nature of belief. What a fully informed interpreter could learn about what a speaker means is all there is to learn; the same goes for what the speaker believes” (Davidson 1983, 148).

  2. 2.

    See Hattiangadi (2017) and Bridges (2017) for two recent instances of this interpretation.

  3. 3.

    See, e.g., Pagin (2001) and Bridges (2006).

  4. 4.

    Note that my focus throughout the paper will be on language rather than thought, but, for Davidson, whatever is true of language is true of thought propositionally conceived. The question what it is for words to mean what they do is equivalent to the question what it is for concepts (conceived as elements of propositional thoughts and attitudes) to have the content they have.

  5. 5.

    As we shall see later, strictly speaking, the theory tells us how words contribute to the meaning of the utterances in which they occur.

  6. 6.

    As I suggested above, and as we shall see, this claim will come to be augmented in the writings on triangulation.

  7. 7.

    See Stroud (2012, 2017). I do not myself believe that Stroud is guilty of the confusion. I have discussed Ginsborg’s “partially reductionist” view in Verheggen (2015) and in Myers and Verheggen (2016, Chap. 2).

  8. 8.

    An exception is Michael Dummett when he was seeking a semantic theory that does not “give the interpretation of the language to someone who already has the concepts required” (Dummett 1975, 102).

  9. 9.

    See Davidson (1967, 35–36), for an initial catalogue of these difficulties.

  10. 10.

    This in effect is an early expression of Davidson’s semantic externalism. For more on this, see Myers and Verheggen (2016, Chap. 3), and Verheggen (2017b), in which I focus on the continuity of Davidson’s semantic externalism, from radical interpretation to triangulation.

  11. 11.

    Radical interpretation has had many detractors, among the most virulent of whom are Fodor and Lepore (1993). Though Davidson has said that the criticisms were sometimes based on misunderstandings, he himself acknowledged that “neither [his] terminology nor [his] views have held absolutely steady” (Davidson 1993, 77 fn2). In a constructive spirit, I am myself putting the best possible spin on the thought experiment.

  12. 12.

    See Davidson (1967, 22–23).

  13. 13.

    Davidson expresses this externalism in many places. See, e.g., Davidson (1987, 29; 1988, 44; 1997, 71).

  14. 14.

    Indeed, this is a question most externalists have not addressed. Cf., e.g., Putnam (1975) and Burge (1986).

  15. 15.

    Davidson makes no sharp distinction among the concepts of belief, objective truth, objectivity, truth, and error. He certainly thinks that one cannot have one of them without having them all. The basic idea is that of having “the concepts of objects and events that occupy a shared world, of objects and events whose properties and existence is [sic] independent of our thought” (Davidson 1991a, 202), or of being aware of “the contrast between true and false, between appearance and reality, mere seeming and being” (Davidson 1991b, 209), where this awareness may be “inarticulately held” (Davidson 1995, 4).

  16. 16.

    Note that Kathrin Glüer recently changed her mind about this. See Glüer (2018, 227).

  17. 17.

    Primitive triangulation is the kind of triangulation even non-linguistic creatures can engage in. It occurs when creatures are reacting simultaneously to each other and to common stimuli in their surroundings, as in Davidson’s example of two lionesses trying to catch a gazelle and coordinating their behaviour by watching each other and the gazelle and reacting to each other’s reactions (Davidson 2001b, 7). Linguistic triangulation is a subset of interpersonal linguistic communication.

  18. 18.

    See also Davidson (1997, 83).

  19. 19.

    Note that the triangulation argument shows that meaning is essentially social, but not essentially communitarian. That is, it shows that, in order to have a language, one must have understood and been understood by others, but one need not mean the same thing as others by the same words. I discuss this further in Myers and Verheggen (2016, Chap. 3).

  20. 20.

    See, e.g., Davidson (1995, 7; 1999, 124).

  21. 21.

    Not every word or concept that refers to an external item must have been used in triangulation for its meaning to be fixed. For instance, “the contents of the belief that a guanaco is present [may have been] determined, not by exposure to guanacos, but by having acquired other words and concepts, such as those of llama, animal, camel, domesticated, and so forth. Somewhere along the line, though, we must come to the direct exposures that anchor thought and language to the world” (Davidson 1991a, 197).

  22. 22.

    I have said more on the continuous aspects of Davidson’s externalism in Myers and Verheggen (2016, Chap. 3).

  23. 23.

    See Talmage (1997), Pagin (2001), Lepore and Ludwig (2005), Bridges (2006), Glüer (2006), Ludwig (2011) and Bernecker (2013).

  24. 24.

    Understood in this way, the triangulation argument becomes much less vulnerable to objections. I have said more about this in Myers and Verheggen (2016, Chap. 1).

  25. 25.

    Thanks to Pedro Rui Abreu, Robert Myers, and Olivia Sultanescu for their comments on an earlier draft of this paper.

References

  • Bernecker, S. (2013). Triangular externalism. In E. Lepore & K. Ludwig (Eds.), A companion to Donald Davidson. Wiley Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bridges, J. (2006). Davidson’s transcendental externalism. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 73(2), 290–315.

    CrossRef  Google Scholar 

  • Bridges, J. (2017). The search for ‘the essence of human language’ in Wittgenstein and Davidson. In Verheggen 2017a.

    Google Scholar 

  • Burge, T. (1986). Cartesian error and the objectivity of perception. In P. Pettit & J. McDowell (Eds.), Subject, thought, and context. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1967). Truth and meaning. In Davidson 1984.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1973). Radical interpretation. In Davidson 1984.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1974a). Belief and the basis of meaning. In Davidson 1984.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1974b). Replies to Lewis and Quine. In Davidson 1984.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1975). Thought and talk. In Davidson 1984.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1982). Rational animals. In Davidson 2001a.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1983). A coherence theory of truth and knowledge. In Davidson 2001a.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1984). Inquiries into truth and interpretation. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1987). Knowing one’s own mind. In Davidson 2001a.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1988). The myth of the subjective. In Davidson 2001a.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1991a). Epistemology externalized. In Davidson 2001a.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1991b). Three varieties of knowledge. In Davidson 2001a.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1992). The second person. In Davidson 2001a.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1993). Reply to Jerry Fodor and Ernest Lepore. In Stoecker 1993.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1995). The objectivity of value. In Davidson 2004.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1997). Indeterminism and antirealism. In Davidson 2001a.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1998). The irreducibility of the concept of self. In Davidson 2001a.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1999). The emergence of thought. In Davidson 2001a.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (2001a). Subjective, intersubjective, objective. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    CrossRef  Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (2001b). Externalisms. In Kotatko et al. 2001.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (2001c). Comments on Karlovy Vary papers. In Kotatko et al. 2001.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (2004). Problems of rationality. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    CrossRef  Google Scholar 

  • Dummett, M. (1975). What is a theory of meaning? In S. Guttenplan (Ed.), Mind and language. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J., & Lepore, E. (1993). Is radical interpretation possible? In Stoecker 1993.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ginsborg, H. (2011). Inside and outside language: Stroud’s nonreductionism about meaning. In J. Bridges, N. Kolodny, & W. Wong (Eds.), The possibility of philosophical understanding: Essays for Barry Stroud. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Glüer, K. (2006). Triangulation. In E. Lepore & B. Smith (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of philosophy of language. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Glüer, K. (2011). Donald Davidson: A short introduction. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    CrossRef  Google Scholar 

  • Glüer, K. (2018). Interpretation and the interpreter. In D. Ball & B. Rabern (Eds.), The science of meaning: Essays on the metatheory of natural language semantics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hattiangadi, A. (2017). The normativity of meaning. In B. Hale, C. Wright, & A. Miller (Eds.), A companion to the philosophy of language (2nd ed.). Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kotatko, P., Pagin, P., & Segal, G. (Eds.). (2001). Interpreting Davidson. Stanford: CSLI.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lepore, E., & Ludwig, K. (2005). Donald Davidson: Meaning, truth, language, and reality. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    CrossRef  Google Scholar 

  • Ludwig, K. (2011). Triangulation triangulated. In C. Amoretti & G. Preyer (Eds.), Triangulation: From an epistemological point of view. Frankfurt: Ontos Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Myers, R. H., & Verheggen, C. (2016). Donald Davidson’s triangulation argument: A philosophical inquiry. New York and London: Routledge.

    CrossRef  Google Scholar 

  • Pagin, P. (2001). Semantic triangulation. In Kotatko et al. 2001.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1975). The meaning of ‘meaning’. In his Language, mind and reality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stoecker, R. (Ed.). (1993). Reflecting Davidson. Berlin, New York: Walter de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stroud, B. (2012). Meaning and understanding. In J. Ellis & D. Guevara (Eds.), Wittgenstein and the philosophy of mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stroud, B. (2017). Davidson and Wittgenstein on meaning and understanding. In Verheggen 2017a.

    Google Scholar 

  • Talmage, C. (1997). Meaning and triangulation. Linguistics and Philosophy, 20, 139–145.

    CrossRef  Google Scholar 

  • Verheggen, C. (2015). Towards a new kind of semantic normativity. International Journal of Philosophical Studies, 23(3), 410–424.

    CrossRef  Google Scholar 

  • Verheggen, C. (Ed.). (2017a). Wittgenstein and Davidson on language, thought, and action. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Verheggen, C. (2017b). Davidson’s semantic externalism: From radical interpretation to triangulation. Special issue for the Centenary of Donald Davidson’s Birth, C. Amoretti, M. de Caro, & F. Ervas (Eds.), Argumenta, 3(1), 145–161.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Claudine Verheggen .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and Permissions

Copyright information

© 2021 Springer Nature Singapore Pte Ltd.

About this chapter

Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Verheggen, C. (2021). The Continuity of Davidson’s Thought: Non-reductionism Without Quietism. In: Yang, S.CM., Myers, R.H. (eds) Donald Davidson on Action, Mind and Value. Logic in Asia: Studia Logica Library. Springer, Singapore. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-981-15-7230-2_8

Download citation