Skip to main content

Contentual and Formal Aspects of Gentzen’s Consistency Proofs

  • Conference paper
  • First Online:
  • 177 Accesses

Part of the book series: Logic in Asia: Studia Logica Library ((LIAA))

Abstract

Gentzen’s 1936 consistency proof for first-order arithmetic (Gentzen, Math Ann, 112:493–565, 1936), located between the first (Gentzen, Archiv für mathematische Logik und Grundlagenforschung, 16:97–118, 1974) and third proofs (Gentzen, Forschungen zur Logik und zur Grundlegung der exakten Wissenschaften, 4:19–44, 1938), was a work during his “transition period 1936–1938.” (Hereafter, we call the first proof the 1935 proof, the second the 1936 proof and the third the 1938 proof.) On the one hand, the 1936 proof inherited from the 1935 proof the method of “finitist (finit)” interpretation for first-order arithmetical formulas.

We would like to express our deep gratitude to Wilfried Sieg for his valuable comments on our work. In particular, we had fruitful discussions when the first author invited him to Waseda University in 2015. In addition, special thanks is due to the anonymous referees for careful readings, many helpful comments, and suggestions. The first author is partially supported by KAKENHI (Grant-in-Aid for Young Scientists (B)) 16K16690. The second author is supported by KAKENHI (Grant-in-Aid for JSPS Fellows) 16J04925.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    [Arai 2002, p. 438].

  2. 2.

    The method of finite notations for infinitary derivations originates from the work by Mints (1978) and has been developed further in subsequent papers by Buchholz (1991, 1997, 2001).

  3. 3.

    Here, we should explain the literatures in more detail. Historically speaking, the first reconstruction of the 1935 proof was by Bernays (1970) and this proof was further discussed by Kreisel in (1971). More recently, this proof was discussed by von Plato in (2009). As to the connection between the 1935 and 1936 proofs, the paper Negri (1980) by Maurizio Negri should be mentioned here. He reconstructed the 1935 proof using ordinals up to \(\varepsilon _{0}\), which would create a close relationship between the 1935 and 1936 proofs. (A similar analysis was given in Sundholm’s Ph.D. thesis Sundholm 1983.) In these papers, authors focused only on mathematical sides of Gentzen’s proofs, while we focus also on a conceptual side of the 1936 proof. Moreover, as we will see in Sect. 5.2, we will investigate a uniform idea behind Gentzen’s three consistency proofs.

    The content of this paper differs from our previous work (Akiyoshi and Takahashi 2013) written in Japanese with respect to the three main points. First, while the aim of Akiyoshi and Takahashi (2013) was to give only a uniform interpretation of Gentzen’s proofs, we also considered questions naturally arising from Sieg’s paper Sieg (2012). Secondly, we use another version of normalization trees, namely, a version of normalization trees reformulated with (possibly) non-well-founded trees. This notion makes it easier to see a connection between the 1936 proof and some notions of intuitionism like spreads and choice sequences. Finally, Sect. 5.3 of the present paper gives another proof of Kreisel’s no-counterexample interpretation, using normalization trees.

  4. 4.

    [Sieg 2012, p. 123].

  5. 5.

    The theory includes the principle of tertium non datur. Hilbert’s aim in this paper was to justify the use of this principle by means of a consistency proof.

  6. 6.

    In fact, Sieg has explained background of not only the 1936 proof but also the 1935 proof. In the present paper, we concentrate on an analysis of the 1936 proof in the light of Sieg’s explanation.

  7. 7.

    As to Hilbert’s exposition of the epsilon substitution method, see Hilbert (1928).

  8. 8.

    Note that Gentzen, in Gentzen (1974), used two-sided sequents. The reason why we formulate (GI) with one-sided sequents is that we use the one-sided sequent calculus in Sects. 3, 4 and 5.

  9. 9.

    Several studies have already pointed out the relationship between Gentzen’s 1935 and 1936 proofs and the no-counterexample interpretation. Cf. Kreisel (1971), Sieg and Parsons (1938), Tait (2005). Furthermore, according to Sieg and Parsons (1938), Tait (2001), the idea of the no-counterexample interpretation is found in Gödel’s notes for his lecture in 1938.

  10. 10.

    In the notation of Hilbert (1931), (TND) is \((x)\mathfrak {A}(x) \vee (Ex)\bar{\mathfrak {A}}(x)\).

  11. 11.

    We owe this outline to Sieg. Cf. [Sieg 2012, pp. 102–105].

  12. 12.

    This English translation is by Sieg.

  13. 13.

    [Sieg 2012, p. 92, p. 103].

  14. 14.

    Cf. [Sieg 2012, p. 107]. Sieg’s explanation can be paraphrased as follows: To apply the rule (\(HR^*\)), one needs to show that \(\mathfrak {A(z)}\) is correct for an arbitrary numeral \(\mathfrak {z}\). Because of Hilbert’s finitist attitude, this must be shown by giving an effective method to verify the correctness of \(\mathfrak {A}(0)\), \(\mathfrak {A}(1)\), \(\mathfrak {A}(2)\) and so on. The concept of an infinite sequence of natural numbers is used here.

  15. 15.

    [Sieg 2012, p. 114].

  16. 16.

    The distinction of purely formal correctness proofs from formal correctness proofs does not matter to our present concern; neither does the distinction of semi-contentual correctness proofs from contentual correctness proofs. Thus we do not consider these distinctions. In the both cases, the former is subsumed into the latter.

  17. 17.

    [Sieg 2012, p. 117].

  18. 18.

    For Gentzen, the statability of a reduction procedure for \(\Gamma \) gives a meaning to \(\Gamma \) from his “finitist” standpoint. It is not easy to estimate the exact strength of Gentzen’s finitist standpoint. As far as we know, his standpoint should be constructive in the following sense. First, all infinite totalities must be generated by some finitary rules (Gentzen 1936, pp. 524–525, 1969, p. 162). For example, the totality of all natural numbers is generated from 0 by the successor rule. Second, one must avoid the use of the principle of the excluded middle for non-decidable predicates (Gentzen 1936, pp. 527–528, 1969, pp. 164–165).

  19. 19.

    Gentzen (1974, p. 103, 1936, p. 549).

  20. 20.

    Cf. [Takeuti 1987, Definition 12.2.].

  21. 21.

    In fact, for the claim that the 1936 proof is both contentual and formal, it is not necessary to show that the main lemma of the 1936 has these consequences. It suffices to show simply that the 1936 proof has both of the features of contentual correctness proofs and formal correctness proofs. Our strategy for the argument in this section comes from the aim of the next section.

  22. 22.

    To formulate reduction steps of the 1936 proof by means of finite notations for infinitary derivations, we need to insert sufficiently many \(\mathsf {E}\)-rules into a given \(\mathsf {Z}\)-derivation h. Moreover, we also need the function \(\phi \) to delete the inserted \(\mathsf {E}\)-rules, since, of course, the proof system Gentzen used to provide the 1936 proof does not include the \(\mathsf {E}\)-rule.

  23. 23.

    Strictly speaking, the above step is a special case of the reduction step that Gentzen formulated in [Gentzen 1936, Sect. 14.25], since he used not the cut-rule such as \(\mathsf {R}_C\) but the “chain-rule (Kettenschluss),” one of whose instances is the cut-rule. Recently, Buchholz analyzed the chain-rule by means of finite notations for infinitary derivations (Buchholz 2015).

  24. 24.

    As to monotone bar induction, see [Troelstra and van Dalen 1988, Chap. 4, Sect. 8].

  25. 25.

    One can read off this idea in Gentzen’s explanation for reduction steps of the 1936 steps. See [Gentzen 1936, Sect. 14.2].

  26. 26.

    In the future works, we will investigate the exact strength of Gentzen’s finitist standpoint and examine whether our argument can be formalized in this standpoint.

  27. 27.

    Here, we slightly changed Buchholz’s actual observation. The actual observation is that for a supposed \(\mathsf {Z}^*_0\)-derivation h of the empty sequent \(\emptyset \), the step \(\phi (h) \mapsto \phi (h[0])\) is a main reduction step of the 1938 proof.

  28. 28.

    For the operational reductions, see [Gentzen 1938, Sect. 3.5].

  29. 29.

    Cf. [Gentzen 1938, Sect. 3.2]. In Gentzen (1969), Szabo translated “Endstück” as “ending”.

  30. 30.

    Cf. Buchholz (1997). Buchholz defined also the function \(\mathsf {hgt}^* (\mathfrak {a})\) of a nominal form \(\mathfrak {a}\), to describe the ordinal assignment in the 1938 proof by means of finite notations for infinitary derivations. Here, we do not need to describe it, so we omit the definition of this function.

  31. 31.

    [Gentzen 1936, pp. 523–524].

  32. 32.

    [Gentzen 1936, p. 526].

  33. 33.

    As to the definition of a boundary inference, we refer to Takeuti’s definition [Takeuti 1987, p. 79].

  34. 34.

    In the future, when we will have more historical resources, we will investigate this point in more detail.

  35. 35.

    The difference is our use of finite notations for infinitary derivations instead of heavy coding.

References

  • Akiyoshi, R. (2010). Gentzen’s first consistency proof revisited. In CARLS series of advanced study of logic and sensibility (Vol. 4, pp. 315–324). Tokyo: Keio University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Akiyoshi, R., & Takahashi, Y. (2013). Reading Gentzen’s three consistency proofs uniformly. (in Japanese) Kagaku kisoron kenkyū (Journal of the Japan Association for Philosophy of Science) 41, 1–22.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arai, T. (2002). Review: Three papers on proof theory by W. Buchholz and S. Tupailo. The Bulletin of Symbolic Logic, 8, 437–439.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bernays, P. (1970). On the original Gentzen consistency proof for number theory. In A. Kino, J. Myhill, & R. Vesley (Eds.), Intuitionism and proof theory. Amsterdam: North-Holland.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buchholz, W. (1991). Notation systems for infinitary derivations. Archive for Mathematical Logic, 30, 277–96.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buchholz, W. (1997). Explaining Gentzen’s consistency proof within infinitary proof theory. In G. Gottlob, A. Leitsch, & D. Mundici (Eds.), Computational logic and proof theory: 5th Kurt Gödel colloquium, KGC’97. Lecture notes in computer science (Vol. 1289, pp. 4–17). Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buchholz, W. (2001). Explaining the Gentzen-Takeuti reduction steps: A second-order system. Archive for Mathematical Logic, 40, 255–72.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buchholz, W. (2010). Another reduction of classical \(ID_{\nu }\) to constructive \(ID^i_{\nu }\)." In Schindler, R. (Eds.), Ways of proof theory (pp. 183–198). Frankfurt: Ontos Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buchholz, W. (2015). On Gentzen’s first consistency proof for arithmetic. In R. Kahle & M. Rathjen (Eds.), Gentzen’s centenary: The quest for consistency (pp. 63–87). Switzerland: Springer International Publishing.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Gentzen, G. (1936). Die Widerspruchsfreiheit der reinen Zahlentheorie. Mathematische Annalen, 112, 493–565.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gentzen, G. (1938). Neue Fassung des Widerspruchsfreiheitsbeweises für die reine Zahlentheorie. Forschungen zur Logik und zur Grundlegung der exakten Wissenschaften, 4, 19–44.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gentzen, G. (1969). In M.E. Szabo (Ed.), The Collected Papers of Gerhard Gentzen. Amsterdam: North-Holland.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gentzen, G. (1974). Der erste Widerspruchsfreiheitsbeweis für die klassische Zahlentheorie. Archiv für mathematische Logik und Grundlagenforschung, 16, 97–118.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gödel, K. (1995). In S. Feferman, J. Dawson, S. Kleene, G. Moore, R. Solovay, & J. van Heijenoort (Eds.), Collected works. III: Unpublished essays and lectures. Oxford: Oxford University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Hilbert, D. (1923). Die logischen Grundlagen der Mathematik. Mathematische Annalen, 88, 151–65.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hilbert, D. (1928). Die Grundlagen der Mathematik. Abhandlungen aus dem Seminar der Hamburgischen Universität, 6, 65–85.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hilbert, D. (1931). Beweis des tertium non datur. Nachrichten von der Gesellschaft der Wissenschaften zu Göttingen, Mathematische-physikalische Klasse (pp. 120–125).

    Google Scholar 

  • Kreisel, G. (1951). On the interpretation of non-finitist proofs - part I. The Journal of Symbolic Logic, 16(4), 241–67.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kreisel, G. (1971). Review: The collected papers of Gerhard Gentzen. by M. E. Szabo. The Journal of Philosophy, 68, 238–65.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mints, G. E. (1978). Finite investigations of transfinite derivations. Journal of Soviet Mathematics, 10, 548–96.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Negri, M. (1980). Constructive sequent reduction in Gentzen’s first consistency proof for arithmetic. In Maria Luisa Dalla Chiara (Ed.), Italian studies in the philosophy of science (pp. 153–68). Dordrecht: D. Reidel Publishing Company.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Schwichtenberg, H. (1977). Proof-theory: Some applications of cut-elimination. In J. Barwise (Ed.), Handbook of mathematical logic (pp. 867–95). Amsterdam: North-Holland.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Sieg, W. (2012). In the shadow of incompleteness: Hilbert and Gentzen. In P. Dybjer, S. Lindström, E. Palmgren, & G. Sundholm (Eds.), Epistemology versus ontology: Essays on the philosophy and foundations of mathematics in honour of Per Martin-Löf (pp. 87–127). London: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Sieg, W., & Parsons, C. (1938). Introductory note to 1938*. In [14, pp. 62–85].

    Google Scholar 

  • Sundholm, G. (1983). Proof theory: A survey of the omega rule. Oxford D. Phil. dissertation.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tait, W. W. (2001). Gödel’s unpublished papers on foundations of mathematics. Philosophia Mathematica 9, 87–126 (2001).

    Google Scholar 

  • Tait, W. W. (2005). Gödel’s reformulation of Gentzen’s first consistency proof for arithmetic: The no-counterexample interpretation. The Bulletin of Symbolic Logic, 11, 225–38.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tait, W. W. (2015). Gentzen’s original consistency proof and the Bar Theorem. In R. Kahle & M. Rathjen (Eds.), Gentzen’s centenary: The quest for consistency (pp. 213–28). Switzerland: Springer International Publishing.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Takeuti, G. (1987). Proof Theory (2nd ed.). Amsterdam: North-Holland.

    Google Scholar 

  • Troelstra, A. S., & van Dalen, D. (1988). Constructivism in mathematics: An introduction (Vol. 1). Amsterdam: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Plato, J. (2009). Gentzen’s original proof of the consistency of arithmetic revisited. In G. Primiero & S. Rahman (Eds.), Acts of knowledge - history, philosophy and logic (pp. 151–71). London: College Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yasugi, M. (1980). Gentzen reduction revisited. Publications of RIMS, 16, 1–33.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Ryota Akiyoshi .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 Springer Nature Singapore Pte Ltd.

About this paper

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this paper

Akiyoshi, R., Takahashi, Y. (2017). Contentual and Formal Aspects of Gentzen’s Consistency Proofs. In: Yang, SM., Lee, K., Ono, H. (eds) Philosophical Logic: Current Trends in Asia. Logic in Asia: Studia Logica Library. Springer, Singapore. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-981-10-6355-8_6

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics