Skip to main content

Proposal-A: wh-Conditionals as Interrogative Conditionals

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Book cover Varieties of Alternatives

Part of the book series: Frontiers in Chinese Linguistics ((FiCL,volume 3))

Abstract

In this chapter, we explore the idea that wh-conditionals are interrogative conditionals.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Three points need mentioning: first, Fine situation semantics of counterfactuals is not concerned with donkey binding but aims at providing a general theory of conditionals just as Stalnaker/Lewis/Kratzer—his main motivation for using situations is to invalidate substitution of logically equivalent antecedents and to validate simplification of disjunctive antecedents. Second, Fine situation-semantics and Kratzer (2012) situation-semantics have many differences (Fine ). But these differences are not relevant for our purposes so we choose to work with Kratzer formulation. Some terminology: whenever Fine says s is a p-state or s exactly verifies p, Kratzer says s exemplifies p. Whenever Fine says s inexactly verifies p, Kratzer says p is true in s (and sometimes we will say s supports p). Finally, to make another simplification, we will talk about exemplifying situations and minimal situations interchangeably, which is justified in our case for we are not going to talk about propositions that are divisive (such as propositions involve mass nouns and negative noun phrases). Standard definition of minimality based on part-of applies for now, but will be revised later.

  2. 2.

    Formally, \(w \models A> C\; if \;u \Vert \!\!\!>\!C\) whenever \(t \Vert \!\!\!-\!A\) and \(t\rightarrow _w u\) (Fine 2012: 237), where > is the counterafactual symbol, \(\Vert \!-\) exact verification, \( \Vert \!\!\!>\) inexact verification, and \(t \rightarrow _{w} u\) means extending t to u according to facts (cf. Kratzer premise set) in w.

  3. 3.

    Two points need mentioning: First, we need the outmost min because we have decided to choose Kratzer-style non-exact situation semantics and classical \(\wedge \). If we were to choose Fine-style exact situation semantics and non-classical \(\wedge \), the min would not be necessary. A non-classical situation semantics \(\wedge \) looks like this: s verifies \(A\wedge B\) iff s is the fusion \(s{_1}\sqcup s{_2}\) of a state \(s_1\) that verifies A and a state \(s_2\) that verifies B. Second, for simplicity, we are making a version of the Limit Assumption and the Unique Assumption (Stalnaker 1968); that is, for any \(s{*}\) there is exactly one maximal premise set that is compatible with p; we write (the conjunction of) the maximal premise set as \(C_{s*}\).

  4. 4.

    For similar uses of non-extensional situation/event semantics of conditionals, see Schwarz (1998) for an analysis of German reduced conditionals that employs a matching relation between situations/events, following Rothstein (1995).

  5. 5.

    We use small capitals to refer to situations. Zhangsan-invited-John-Mary-&-Lisi-invited-John-Mary-Sue is the situation that exemplifies/minimally-supports the proposition that Zhangsan invited John and Mary, and Lisi invited John, Mary and Sue.

  6. 6.

    min \(_\#\) is related to one of the two aspects of minimality—the individual minimality—discussed in Van Benthem (1989). Individual minimality itself comes from Logic Programming (Lloyd 2012). For instance, Prolog programs are supposed to ‘contain no individuals/objects except for those which are explicitly named in the language of the program’ (Van Benthem 1989: 334).

  7. 7.

    Formalizing \(\textsc {No.Old}\) is doable. First, we take the set of situations that support the presuppositions of \(Q_A\) and \(Q_C\)\(\{ s: \textsc {pre}(Q_A)(s) \wedge \textsc {pre}(Q_A)(s)\}\). We then apply min \(_\#\) to the set as what we did to \(S{_{13}}\); this gives us the unit set \( \{\textsc {Zs-inivted-Ls- \& -Ls-invited-Zs}\} \) =min \(_\#\{ s: \textsc {pre}(Q_A)(s) \wedge \textsc {pre}(Q_A)(s)\}\). Finally, \(\textsc {No.Old}\) in the case of \(S{_{13}}\) requires that none of the situations in \(S{_{13}}\) contain a subsituation that itself is a subsituation of any situation in min \(_\#\{ s: \textsc {pre}(Q_A)(s) \wedge \textsc {pre}(Q_A)(s)\}\). This is complicated, and I believe an intuitive understanding of \(\textsc {No.Old}\) suffices.

  8. 8.

    Here is an example:

    figure u
  9. 9.

    Our account is compatible with other ways of capturing the mention-some reading of questions, such as by appealing to pragmatic principles or partial answers. See Dayal (2016\(Sect.\,\) 3) for relevant discussion.

References

  • Beck, S. 2012. Pluractional comparisons. Linguistics and Philosophy 35 (1): 57–110.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beck, S., and H. Rullmann. 1999. A flexible approach to exhaustivity in questions. Natural Language Semantics 7 (3): 249–298.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Berman, S. 1987. Situation-based semantics for adverbs of quantification. In Studies in semantics, vol. 12, ed. J. Blevins, and A. Vainikka, 46–68., University of Massachusetts Occasional Papers in Linguistics Amherst: GLSA, University of Massachusetts.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cheng, L.L., and C.J. Huang. 1996. Two types of donkey sentences. Natural Language Semantics 4 (2): 121–163.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chierchia, G., and H.-C. Liao. 2014. Where do chinese wh-items fit? In Epistemic indefinites: Exploring modality beyond the verbal domain.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chierchia, G. 2013. Logic in grammar. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dayal, V. 1996. Locality in wh Quantification. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dayal, V. 2016. Questions. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Elbourne, P.D. 2005. Situations and individuals. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fine, K. 2012. Counterfactuals without possible worlds. The Journal of Philosophy.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fine, K. Truthmaker semantics. In Blackwell companion to the philosophy of language. Blackwell. To appear.

    Google Scholar 

  • Groenendijk, J., and M. Stokhof. 1982. Semantic analysis of wh-complements. Linguistics and Philosophy 5 (2): 175–233.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haida, A. 2008. The indefiniteness and focusing of wh-words. In Semantics and Linguistic Theory 18.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hamblin, C.L. 1973. Questions in Montague English. Foundations of Language 10: 41–53.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heim, I. 1990. E-type pronouns and donkey anaphora. Linguistics and Philosophy.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heim, I. 1994. Interrogative semantics and Karttunen’s semantics for know. In Proceedings of IATL 1.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huang, C.-T.J. 1982. Logical relations in Chinese and the theory of grammar. PhD thesis, MIT, Cambridge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huang, Y. 2010. On the form and meaning of Chinese bare conditionals: Not just whatever. PhD thesis, The University of Texas, Austin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Karttunen, L., and S. Peters. 1976. What indirect questions conventionally implicate. In CLS 11.

    Google Scholar 

  • Karttunen, L. 1977. Syntax and semantics of questions. Linguistics and Philosophy 1 (1): 3–44.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kiss, K.É. 1995. Introduction. In Discourse configurational languages, ed. K.É. Kiss.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kratzer, A. 1979. Conditional necessity and possibility. In Semantics from different points of view, 117–147. Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kratzer, A. 1981a. The notional category of modality. In Words, worlds, and contexts, 38–74.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kratzer, A. 1981b. Partition and revision: The semantics of counterfactuals. Journal of Philosophical Logic 10 (2): 201–206.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kratzer, A. 2012. Modals and conditionals. vol. 36. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kratzer, A. 2014. Situations in natural language semantics. In The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy, ed. E.N. Zalta. Spring. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2014/entries/situations-semantics/.

  • Lewis, D. 1973. Counterfactuals. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. 1981. Ordering semantics and premise semantics for counterfactuals. Journal of Philosophical Logic 10 (2): 217–234.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lloyd, J.W. 2012. Foundations of logic programming. Springer Science & Business Media.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reinhart, T. 1997. Quantifier scope: How labor is divided between qr and choice functions. Linguistics and Philosophy 20 (4): 335–397.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rooth, M. 1992. A theory of focus interpretation. Natural Language Semantics 1 (1).

    Google Scholar 

  • Rothstein, S. 1995. Adverbial quantification over events. Natural Language Semantics 3 (1): 1–31.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schwarz, B. 1998. Reduced conditionals in german: Event quantification and definiteness. Natural Language Semantics 6 (3): 271–301.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stalnaker, R. 1968. A theory of conditionals. In Studies in logical theory, ed. N. Rescher., American Philosophical Quarterly Monograph Series 2 Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stalnaker, R. 1975. Indicative conditionals. Philosophia.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Benthem, J. 1989. Semantic parallels in natural language and computation. In Logic colloquium. Cranada 1987, ed. E. HD, 331–375. Elservier.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Fintel, K. 1994. Restrictions on quantifier domains. PhD thesis, University of Massachusetts, Amherst.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Fintel, K. 2004. A minimal theory of adverbial quantification. In Context dependence in the analysis of linguistic meaning, ed. H.K.B. Partee, 137–175. Amsterdam: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Mingming Liu .

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2018 Peking University Press and Springer Nature Singapore Pte Ltd.

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Liu, M. (2018). Proposal-A: wh-Conditionals as Interrogative Conditionals. In: Varieties of Alternatives. Frontiers in Chinese Linguistics, vol 3. Springer, Singapore. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-981-10-6208-7_6

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-981-10-6208-7_6

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Singapore

  • Print ISBN: 978-981-10-6207-0

  • Online ISBN: 978-981-10-6208-7

  • eBook Packages: Social SciencesSocial Sciences (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics