Advertisement

Wittgenstein and the Path of Learning

  • Michael Luntley
Chapter

Abstract

In this essay, I defend an individualistic reading of Wittgenstein on learning . Many scholars (Williams, Stickney, Simpson) read Wittgenstein as endorsing a broadly social initiation model of learning (see also, Derry and Bakhurst for a Vygotskian spin on this). The social initiation model looks inevitable if you endorse the orthodox assumptions about Wittgenstein’s treatment of linguistic regularity. The key assumptions are as follows: (i) linguistic regularity involves a normative practice with words; (ii) normativity is socially constituted; and (iii) learning involves acquiring these normative practices. Developing arguments started in my Wittgenstein : Opening Investigations (2015), I deny all three assumptions. Wittgenstein’s treatment of linguistic regularity is naturalistic, not normative; it involves users engaging with words in ways that are patterned, patterns in which words fit, but the concept of ‘fit’ requires no more than ‘primitive normativity ’ (Ginsborg 2011). What this amounts to is the following: learners ’ first encounters with things from which they acquire concepts are encounters shaped by the syntactic patterns that render things salient, patterns of rhythm, rhyme and repetition. These patterns are not the patterns of conceptual order, let alone a normative pattern; they are the patterns characteristic of aesthetic experience; they are the patterns of play and of games. In short, individuals learn by playing with the forms of aesthetic experience—playing with sounds and symbols is the basis for these things coming to bear content. This is not to deny that there is a transition from such patterns to conceptual patterns, but challenging the orthodoxy of assumption (i) leaves conceptual patterns inheriting much of the contingency of the shape of aesthetic patterns. In the Big Typescript , Wittgenstein compares a rule to a garden path. We walk paths with a sense of allegiance to the way to go, but without any prescriptive sense that we have to go this way rather than that. We are, in part, authors of the paths we take. Understanding Wittgenstein on learning involves coming to learn how to share his sense of being comfortable with the contingencies of word use and to stop looking for any sense that there are prescriptive norms governing what we learn to do with words.

Keywords

Learning Primitive normativity Rules Know-how Imagination Aesthetic 

References

  1. Baker, G. P., & Hacker, P. M. S. (1980/2005). Wittgenstein—Understanding and meaning, volume 1 of an analytical commentary on the Philosophical Investigations. Oxford: Blackwell; 2nd edition in two volumes revised and edited by Hacker: Wittgenstein: Understanding and meaning; Part 1—Essays, Oxford: Blackwell (2005) and, Wittgenstein: Understanding and meaning; Part II Exegesis (pp. 1–184). Oxford: Blackwell (2005).Google Scholar
  2. Bakhurst, D. (2011). The formation of reason. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Boghossian, P. (2003). The normativity of content. Philosophical Issues, 13, 31–45.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Boghossian, P. (2005). Is meaning normative? In A. Beckermann & C. Nimtz (Eds.), Philosophy—Science—Scientific philosophy. Mentis: Paderborn.Google Scholar
  5. Carey, S. (2009). The origin of concepts. Oxford & New York: OUP.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Child, W. (2010). Wittgenstein. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
  7. Derry, J. (2013). Vygotsky: Philosophy and education. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Evans, G. (1982). The varieties of reference. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
  9. Fodor, J. (1975). The language of thought. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  10. Ginsborg, H. (2011). Rule-following and primitive normativity. Journal of Philosophy, CVIII, 5, 227–254.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Hattiangadi, A. (2006). Is meaning normative? Mind and Language, 21(2), 220–240.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Hattiangadi, A. (2007). Oughts and thoughts: Rule following and the normativity of content. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Huemer, W. (2006). The transition from causes to norms: Wittgenstein on training. Grazer Philosophiche Studien, 71, 205–225.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Kripke, S. (1982). Wittgenstein on rules and private language. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  15. Luntley, M. (2008). Training and learning. Educational Philosophy and Theory, 40(5), 695–711.Google Scholar
  16. Luntley, M. (2012). Training, training, training: The making of second nature and the roots of Wittgenstein’s pragmatism. European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy. Symposia: Wittgenstein and Pragmatism a Reassessment, IV(2), 88–104.Google Scholar
  17. Luntley, M. (2015). Wittgenstein: Opening investigation. Oxford & Malden: Wiley-Blackwell.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Luntley, M. (2016a). Forgetski Vygotsky, Educational Philosophy and Theory (forthcoming).Google Scholar
  19. Luntley, M. (2016b). What’s the problem with Dewey? European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy (special number on centenary of Dewey’s Democracy and Education), VIII(1), 77–99.Google Scholar
  20. McDowell, J. (1994). Mind and world. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University PressGoogle Scholar
  21. McGinn, M. (2013). The Routledge guidebook to the philosophical investigations (2nd ed.). London: Routledge (1st ed. 1997).Google Scholar
  22. Pears, D. (1998). The false prison (Vol. 2). Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
  23. Pears, D. (2006) Paradox and platitude in Wittgenstein’s philosophy. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
  24. Simpson, D. (2014). Wittgenstein and stage-setting: Being brought into the space of reasons. Educational Philosophy and Theory, 46(6), 624–639.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. Smeyers, P., & Burbules, N. (2006). Education as initiation into practices. Educational Theory, 56, 439–449.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. Stern, D. (2004). Wittgenstein’s Philosophical Investigations: An introduction. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Stickney, J. (2008). Training and mastery of techniques in Wittgenstein’s later philosophy. Educational Philosophy and Theory, 40(5).Google Scholar
  28. Travis, C. (2008). Occasion-sensitivity. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. Travis, C. (2011). Objectivity and the Parochial. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  30. Wiggins, D. (2012). Practical knowledge: Knowing how to and knowing that. Mind, 121, 97–130.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. Williams, M. (1994). The significance of learning in Wittgenstein’s later philosophy. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 24, 173–204.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  32. Williams, M. (2002). Wittgenstein, mind and meaning: Towards a social conception of mind. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
  33. Williams, M. (2010). Blind obedience: Paradox and learning in the later Wittgenstein. London & New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
  34. Williams, M. (2011). Master and novice in the later Wittgenstein. American Philosophical Quarterly, 48(2), 199–211.Google Scholar
  35. Wittgenstein, L. (1968). Philosophical investigations (3rd ed., G.E.M. Anscombe, Trans.). Oxford: Basil Blackwell (PI §, or PI, pg.). Google Scholar
  36. Wittgenstein, L. (2005). The big typescript TS213 (C. G. Luckhardt & M. A. E. Aue. Ed. & Trans.,) Oxford: Blackwell (BT).Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Nature Singapore Pte Ltd. 2017

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of PhilosophyUniversity of WarwickCoventryUK

Personalised recommendations