Wittgenstein and Classical Pragmatism

Chapter

Abstract

My paper compares Wittgenstein to the three classical pragmatist, Charles Sanders Peirce, William James , and John Dewey . It is well known that Frank Ramsey read and cited Peirce, although we can only conjecture what, if anything, he may have communicated of Peirce to Wittgenstein or if Wittgenstein ever read him for himself. Through Ramsey, we will explore some of the similarities between Wittgenstein and Peirce, including the typically pragmatist emphasis on intelligent action and its relation to doubt. One important difference is Peirce and pragmatism’s emphasis on embodied habits. We will also examine the well-documented influence of James on Wittgenstein. Many of Wittgenstein’s criticisms of psychology can most likely be traced to errors he initially found in James. However, there are many likely sources of positive influence on Wittgenstein as well including perhaps the notion of an inherited world picture, his unique theory of universals along with his holism, historicism, and anti-foundationalism . While Wittgenstein has many positive things to say about James , he is entirely negative in his remarks about Dewey. Ironically, we will find that Dewey is the pragmatist with whom most commentators have identified thematic resonances to Wittgenstein.

Keywords

Pragmatism Peirce James Dewey Wittgenstein 

References

  1. Bouwsma, O. K. (1986). Wittgenstein: Conversations, 19491951. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett.Google Scholar
  2. Dewey, J. (2003). The later works, 1925–1953. In Jo Ann Boydston (Ed.), The collected works of John Dewey, 1882–1953, (Vol. 4: 1929). Carbondale and Edwardsville: Southern Illinois University Press.Google Scholar
  3. Dewey, J. (1871–1952). References to correspondence are to The correspondence of John Dewey, 1871–1952 (I–IV). Electronic Edition.Google Scholar
  4. Goodman, R. B. (2002). Wittgenstein and William James. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. James, W. References are to The works of William James (17 Vols.). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press: Principles of psychology (3 Vols.) (1890/1981). The third volume is a compendium (PP I and II). Varieties of religious experience (1902/1985) (VRE). Pragmatism (1907/1975) (P). A Pluralistic Universe (1909/1977) (PU). “Percept and concept” In Some problems of philosophy (1911/1979) (PC).Google Scholar
  6. Johnson, M. (2007). The meaning of the body: Aesthetics of human understanding. Chicago, IL: The University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Nubiola, J. (1996). Scholarship on the relations between Ludwig Wittgenstein and Charles S. Peirce. In I. Angelelli & M. Cerezo (Eds.), Proceedings of the III symposium on history of logic. Gruyter: Berlin.Google Scholar
  8. Ogden, C. K., & Richards, I. A. (1923/1989). The meaning of meaning. New York, NY: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, Inc.Google Scholar
  9. Peirce, C. References are to The essential Peirce (2 Vols.) (Indiana University Press, 1992, 1998). Page numbers follow the volume number in EP references. All other references are to the Collected papers of Charles S. Peirce (8 Vols.) (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1931–58). Paragraph numbers follows the volume number in CP references.Google Scholar
  10. Quine, W. V. (1953). Two dogmas of empiricism. In From a logical point of view (pp. 20–46). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  11. Quine, W. V. (1969). Ontological relativity. In W. V. Quine (Ed.), Ontological relativity and other essays (pp. 26–68). New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
  12. Ramsey, F. P. (1923/2013). Critical notice of L. Wittgenstein’s “Tractatus logico-philosophicus.” In R. B. Braithwaite (Ed.), The foundations of mathematics. Mansfield Centre, CT: Martino Publishing.Google Scholar
  13. Ramsey, F. P. (1926/1990). Truth and probability. In D. H. Mellor (Ed.), Philosophical papers F.P. Ramsey. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  14. Ramsey, F. P. (1929/1990). General propositions and causality. In D. H. Mellor (Ed.), Philosophical papers F.P. Ramsey. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  15. Rorty, R. (1979). Philosophy and the mirror of nature. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  16. Williams, B. (1974). Wittgenstein and idealism. In G. Vesey (Ed.), Understanding Wittgenstein. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
  17. Wittgenstein, L. (1922). Tractatus logico-philosophicus. New York, NY: Harcourt, Brace & Company (TLP).Google Scholar
  18. Wittgenstein, L. (1953). Philosophical investigations. New York: The Macmillan Company (PI).Google Scholar
  19. Wittgenstein, L. (1967). Zettel. (G. E. M. Anscombe, Trans.). Oxford: Basil Blackwell (Z).Google Scholar
  20. Wittgenstein, L. (1972). On certainty. New York: Harper & Row (OC).Google Scholar
  21. Wittgenstein, L. (1974). Letters to Russell, Keynes and Moore (G. H. von Wright assisted by B. F. McGuinness, Eds.). Oxford: Basil Blackwell (LRKM).Google Scholar
  22. Wittgenstein, L. (1978). Remarks on the foundations of mathematics. Oxford: Basil Blackwell (RFM).Google Scholar
  23. Wittgenstein, L. (1980). Culture and value. (G. H. von Wright Ed., in collaboration with H. Nyman and P. Winch, Trans.). Oxford: Basil Blackwell (CV).Google Scholar
  24. Wittgenstein, L. (1988). Wittgenstein’s lectures on philosophical psychology 1946–47, notes by P. T. Geach, K. J. Shah & A. C. Jackson; P.T. Geach (Ed.). Hassocks: Harvester Press (LPP).Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Nature Singapore Pte Ltd. 2017

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Virginia TechBlacksburgUSA

Personalised recommendations