Skip to main content

Violence in International Criminal Law and Beyond

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
  • 326 Accesses

Part of the book series: International Criminal Justice Series ((ICJS,volume 31))

Abstract

This chapter examines the increasing potential of international criminal law to advance hegemonic claims over the meaning of concepts relevant beyond its own field. By building on the Gramscian conceptualisation of hegemony and the role of law therein, I suggest that international criminal law advances a certain understanding of violence, that obscures and normalises types of violence that are beyond its gaze. The power of international criminal law to advance strong claims is, in turn, based on its asserted relevance for the causes of global justice, lasting peace and punishing the most serious crimes.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Weigend 2008, p. 936.

  2. 2.

    Wells 2001, pp. 15–16; Duff 2007, p. 44; deGuzman 2020, p. 31.

  3. 3.

    Rajkovic 2020, p. 65.

  4. 4.

    Ibid., p. 72.

  5. 5.

    I use the term ‘international criminal law stricto sensu’ to refer to the law pertaining to the four core crimes, since the scope of international criminal law is subject to varying interpretations in the scholarship, and I adhere to a broad definition of international criminal law whereby the definition on an international crime is not limited to the core crimes—the term international criminal law stricto sensu, therefore, is helpful in referring to the part of international criminal law related to core crimes. The terms international criminal law stricto sensu and international criminal law largo sensu can be said to correspond conceptually to the two distinct terms in Roman and Germanic languages: ‘droit international pénal’, ‘derecho internacional penal’ and ‘Völkerstrafrecht’ are similar in scope to international criminal law stricto sensu, whereas international criminal law largo sensu, or international criminal law interpreted broadly, corresponds to ‘droit pénal international’, ‘derecho penal internacional’ and ‘Internationales Strafrecht’ respectively—see Werle and Jessberger 2020, p. 35.

    Many authors, including Werle and Jessberger 2020; Cassese 2008, pp. 3–4; Cryer 2010, p. 5 reserve the term international criminal law to refer to a body of rules concerning the core crimes. The other international crimes, or the so-called treaty crimes (transnational organised crime, terrorist offences, corruption, various trafficking offences, etc.), following this definition of international criminal law, fall into a relatively recent category of transnational criminal law. Scholars, influential in the field of international criminal law prior to this conceptual divergence, most notably M. Cherif Bassiouni, understood international criminal law primarily as international criminal law largo sensu, see Bassiouni 2013, pp. 1–57. For a discussion of the international/transnational criminal law divide and its implications for the discipline, see Guilfoyle 2020; Mégret 2020. For a critique of these varying approaches to international criminal law scope ratione materiae, see Baars 2019, pp. 243–263.

  6. 6.

    Hegemony as an analytic concept is used, in particular, to theorise a dominant position of a state in the international system; it is also understood as a discursive practice. However, it is within Marxist theoretical framework that allows not only to identify hegemony, but also to explain the reasons for its emergence in the particular place and time by analysing the material basis thereof, see Knox 2019.

  7. 7.

    Miéville 2005, p. 88.

  8. 8.

    Marks 2008, p. 2.

  9. 9.

    Cutler 2005, p. 534.

  10. 10.

    Morton 2007, p. 96.

  11. 11.

    Gramsci 2007, p. 340.

  12. 12.

    Cutler 2005, p. 536.

  13. 13.

    Morton 2007, p. 93.

  14. 14.

    Knox 2019, p. 356, emphasis in the original. Nicos Poulantzas has thus argued about the role of law in constructing hegemony: ‘[i]t is exactly as if the abstract, formal and general character of law had rendered it the mechanism most suitable for fulfilling the key function of every dominant ideology: namely, of cementing together the social formation under the aegis of the dominant class’ in Poulantzas 1980, pp. 87–88.

  15. 15.

    Cutler 2005, p. 536.

  16. 16.

    Rajkovic 2020, p. 74.

  17. 17.

    Morton 2007, p. 69.

  18. 18.

    One of the most well-known international relations scholars employing Gramsci’s concept of hegemony and an influential figure in international political economy is Robert Cox, see, e.g., Cox 1981; Cox 1983.

  19. 19.

    The concept of hegemony has been widely used in the international relations literature (particularly in realist accounts) to analyse power relations among states—see Knox 2019, pp. 334–336. I do not engage with the concept of hegemony so understood.

  20. 20.

    deGuzman 2020, pp. 22, 26.

  21. 21.

    Mégret 2014, p. 19.

  22. 22.

    Tallgren 2014, p. 76.

  23. 23.

    Knox 2019, p. 351.

  24. 24.

    Similarly, it is suggested by Werle and Jessberger that international criminal law draws a special ‘supranational legitimacy’ from the fact that it protects the interests of the international community that are attacked when an international crime is committed, Werle and Jessberger 2020, pp. 38–39.

  25. 25.

    Nouwen 2012, p. 342.

  26. 26.

    The universalisation of norms, values, and other elements of ideology, Knox argues, ‘has a material foundation in the universalizing and abstracting tendencies of capitalism, tendencies reproduced in international law’, Knox 2019, p. 358.

  27. 27.

    Moreno-Ocampo 2007, p. 216.

  28. 28.

    Assembly of States Parties of the International Criminal Court, 6th Session, Remarks of the Prosecutor, 30 November 2007, https://asp.icc-cpi.int/iccdocs/asp_docs/library/asp/Statement_Prosecutor_en_30Nov2007.pdf. Accessed 19 January 2022. Assembly of States Parties of the International Criminal Court, 6th Session, Remarks of the Secretary-General of the United Nations, 3 December 2007, https://asp.icc-cpi.int/iccdocs/asp_docs/library/asp/statement_SG_6thasp_3_Dec_2007.pdf. Accessed 17 February 2022. Office of the Prosecutor (2021) ICC Prosecutor, Fatou Bensouda, Meets with the EU Foreign Affairs Ministers: “The ICC Is Central to a More Just and Rules-Based International System”. https://www.icc-cpi.int/Pages/item.aspx?name=pr1569. Accessed 12 May 2021

  29. 29.

    Parmentier 2003, p. 204; deGuzman 2020, pp. 6, 22, 89; Mégret 2015, p. 77; Kendall 2015, p. 113; Nouwen and Werner 2015, p. 157.

  30. 30.

    Mégret 2015, p. 78.

  31. 31.

    Schwöbel-Patel 2021, p. 15.

  32. 32.

    ‘Justice’ in Lexico Dictionaries powered by Oxford https://www.lexico.com/definition/justice. Accessed 12 May 2021.

  33. 33.

    At the same time, I do not necessarily suggest that the use to the term ‘global justice’ by practitioners, scholars, and civil society representatives is consciously aimed at establishing and maintaining hegemony—the operations of ideology are much more complex.

  34. 34.

    Nouwen 2012, p. 343; Nouwen and Werner 2015, p. 163.

  35. 35.

    Krever 2013, p. 703; Kendall 2015, p. 114.

  36. 36.

    I will go back to the concept of social justice and its meaning in the subsequent discussion of violence.

  37. 37.

    Ratner 2015, pp. 19–20.

  38. 38.

    While there is by now a vibrant discussion on various moral philosophical and ethical questions pertaining to international criminal law, it is noteworthy that the international criminal law practice and scholarship hardly engage with the philosophical literature on global justice, see Schwöbel-Patel 2021, p. 14.

  39. 39.

    Werle and Jessberger 2020, p. 38; Nouwen 2012, p. 331.

  40. 40.

    Nouwen and Werner 2015, p. 162; McAuliffe and Schwöbel-Patel 2018, pp. 995, 998.

  41. 41.

    Nouwen and Werner 2015, p. 168.

  42. 42.

    Preambular paras 3 and 4 state:

    ‘Recognizing that such grave crimes threaten the peace, security and well-being of the world, Affirming that the most serious crimes of concern to the international community as a whole must not go unpunished and that their effective prosecution must be ensured by taking measures at the national level and by enhancing international cooperation…’, ICC Statute.

  43. 43.

    Assembly of States Parties of the International Criminal Court, 5th Session. Opening Remarks of the President of the Court, 23 November 2006, https://www.icc-cpi.int/NR/rdonlyres/3EEF266E-E4B1-486C-9B05-DD0D87CDBEEB/143883/PK_20061123_en1.pdf, p. 2. Accessed 19 January 2022.

  44. 44.

    Nouwen and Werner 2010; Nielsen 2008, p. 81; Nouwen 2012; Krever 2014a, p. 85.

  45. 45.

    Nouwen 2012, pp. 332, 335.

  46. 46.

    Royer 2017, p. 404.

  47. 47.

    Nouwen 2012, p. 339.

  48. 48.

    A detailed investigation of the normative content of the concept of gravity, its use and legitimating role in international criminal law is provided by deGuzman 2020. On the reliance of international criminal law on the concept of gravity, see p. 2.

  49. 49.

    Preamble, ICC Statute.

  50. 50.

    Schabas 2017, pp. 74–75; for an opposite view, see O’Keefe 2015, pp. 57–58, who argues that an idea that gravity can serve as an identifying feature of international crimes is ‘misleading’.

  51. 51.

    Schabas 2017, pp. 182, 186.

  52. 52.

    Ibid., p. 325.

  53. 53.

    Kalpouzos and Mann 2015, pp. 3, 24; deGuzman 2020, p. 61; Rajkovic 2020, p. 84.

  54. 54.

    Situation on Registered Vessels of the Comoros, the Hellenic Republic of Greece and the Kingdom of Cambodia (ICC-01/13), Decision on the request of the Union of the Comoros to review the Prosecutor’s decision not to initiate an investigation, 16 July 2015, para 21, as quoted in Schabas 2017, p. 186.

  55. 55.

    Schwöbel-Patel 2020, pp. 781–782; Guilfoyle 2020, pp. 791, 794, 799; Mégret 2020, pp. 815–817.

  56. 56.

    deGuzman 2020, p. 47.

  57. 57.

    Mégret 2014, p. 23.

  58. 58.

    This term was coined by the US representative at the Rome Conference David Scheffer, as quoted in Royer 2017, p. 407.

  59. 59.

    Tallgren 2002, p. 564; see also Kendall 2015, p. 125.

  60. 60.

    Tallgren 2002, p. 595; Schwöbel-Patel 2020, p. 769.

  61. 61.

    Carvalho 2019, p. 9.

  62. 62.

    ICC Statute, Articles 5–8.

  63. 63.

    See, e.g., Situation in the Republic of Kenya (Decision Pursuant to Article 15 of the ICC Statute on the Authorization of an Investigation into the Situation in the Republic of Kenya) ICC-01/09-19 (31 March 2010), para 84.

  64. 64.

    deGuzman 2020, p. 72.

  65. 65.

    ICC 2013, Elements of Crimes, pp. 2–3, https://www.icc-cpi.int/Publications/Elements-of-Crimes.pdf. Accessed 19 January 2022.

  66. 66.

    ICC Statute, Article 7.

  67. 67.

    Kalpouzos and Mann 2015, pp. 1–5.

  68. 68.

    ILC, Report on the Work of Its Thirty-Sixth Session, 7 May–27 July 1984, UN Doc. A/39/10, para 63, as quoted in deGuzman 2020, p. 48.

  69. 69.

    Schwöbel-Patel 2020, p. 788.

  70. 70.

    Ibid.

  71. 71.

    Anghie and Chimni 2004, p. 193.

  72. 72.

    Nielsen 2008; Schwöbel-Patel 2020, p. 784.

  73. 73.

    Tzouvala 2020, pp. 64–66.

  74. 74.

    In this section I provide some examples of low-tech and high-tech violence. For a further discussion on this point, see Tallgren 2014, p. 74.

  75. 75.

    Nielsen 2008, p. 97; Torrens 2020, p. 76.

  76. 76.

    Krever 2014a, pp. 83–84, 88.

  77. 77.

    ICC Statute, Articles 25, 28.

  78. 78.

    Nielsen 2008, pp. 98, 106. One of the proofs of the particularity of the Western concept of penal laws—against the purported universality of individual responsibility—is provided by Steven Humphreys, who notes that criminal law was one of the main instruments of the imperialist powers in constructing governable units in their colonial territories, where imprisonment as a form of punishment was virtually unknown until the late 19th century—see Humphreys 2010, p. 117.

  79. 79.

    Werle 2007, p. 957.

  80. 80.

    Violence was investigated, among others, by Jacques Derridà, Walter Benjamin and Michel Foucault. For a brief overview of these thinkers' takes on violence, see Antiphon 2009.

  81. 81.

    Farmer 2003.

  82. 82.

    Nixon 2011.

  83. 83.

    Galtung 1969, p. 168. It should be noted that, in so far as the main focus of Galtung’s research is peace, and the concept of violence appears to be instrumental to the study of the concept of peace, Galtung does not develop the theory elaborated in this article much in his subsequent work.

  84. 84.

    Galtung 1969, p. 168, emphasis in original.

  85. 85.

    Ibid., p. 169.

  86. 86.

    The violence of preventable deaths or severely compromised life quality is discussed at length by Farmer 2003. Among a variety of case-studies he considers, inter alia, the deaths from antibiotic-resistant tuberculosis in Russian prisons in the 1990s.

  87. 87.

    Galtung 1969, p. 170.

  88. 88.

    Ibid., p. 171.

  89. 89.

    Ibid., p. 173. In subsequent works, Galtung distinguished the third type of violence—cultural violence, that is embodied in language, patterns of reasoning, symbols, etc.—see, e.g., Galtung 2013a.

  90. 90.

    Galtung 1969, pp. 172, 183.

  91. 91.

    Ibid., p. 171.

  92. 92.

    Galtung 2013b, p. 37.

  93. 93.

    Ibid.

  94. 94.

    The outcome of the existing division of labour, he suggests, is ‘[s]tructural violence all over the place; among and within countries’, see Galtung 2013a, p. 55, footnote in the original omitted.

  95. 95.

    Galtung 1969, p. 173, emphasis in italics in original, emphasis in bold added.

  96. 96.

    Carvalho suggests, in this regard, that ‘…the same processes that make visible and naturalise the individualised violence of crime also blind us to other, more pervasive—and, one could argue, more dangerous—kinds of violence upon which criminalisation depends. These include the structural violence embedded in contemporary societies, which preserves and promotes structures of inequality that, among many other things, protect patriarchal structures and socio-economic exploitation, and the epistemic violence that makes society see and treat racialised and marginalised populations as dangerous criminals first, and human beings second—if at all’ in Carvalho 2019, p. 12.

  97. 97.

    Žižek 2009, p. 2.

  98. 98.

    Nixon 2011, p. 11.

  99. 99.

    Galtung 2013a, p. 41.

  100. 100.

    Ibid., p. 56.

  101. 101.

    Galtung 1969, p. 178.

  102. 102.

    Butler discusses concepts of recognisability and frame of recognition and Butler 2009, pp. 3–7.

  103. 103.

    Ibid., p. 6.

  104. 104.

    Ibid., p. 5.

  105. 105.

    Marks 2011, p. 75, emphasis added.

  106. 106.

    Krever 2014b, pp. 130–131.

  107. 107.

    Simpson 2014, p. 170.

  108. 108.

    As Tallgren suggests, ‘[a]n even more fundamental question is whether criminal law could ever be able to provide closure to large-scale, deep-rooted injustice and suffering, and whether the expectation of finality after a criminal trial has established the truth by identifying the guilty could in fact violently silence other truths, other kinds of responsibilities’, Tallgren 2002, p. 593.

  109. 109.

    McAuliffe and Schwöbel-Patel 2018, p. 1001.

  110. 110.

    Krever 2014b, p. 129.

  111. 111.

    Poulantzas argues that law in the capitalist mode of production assumes a leading role in ideology, the role previously occupied by religion: ‘The centre of legitimacy shifts away from the sacred towards legality… and juridical-political ideology supplants religious ideology as the predominant forum’, in Poulantzas 1980, p. 87. See also Krever 2014b, p. 131.

  112. 112.

    Krever 2014b, p. 131.

  113. 113.

    Ibid., p. 129; Schwöbel-Patel 2021, p. 56.

  114. 114.

    Gevers 2014, p. 231.

  115. 115.

    Krever 2013, p. 720; Burgis-Kasthala 2014, p. 252; Gevers 2014, pp. 232–233.

  116. 116.

    The hard lot of international criminal lawyers has been thus formulated by Werle: ‘the collective nature of crimes under international law does not absolve us of the need to determine individual responsibility’, Werle 2007, p. 953.

  117. 117.

    The distinction between intended and unintended violence is another axis along which Galtung maps violence, which, however, seems closely tied to the distinction between direct and indirect violence: in the absence of a subject exerting violence, there can be no intention in structural violence, see Galtung 1969, p. 171.

  118. 118.

    Esenin undated.

  119. 119.

    Schwöbel-Patel 2021, p. 41.

  120. 120.

    Ibid., p. 59.

  121. 121.

    Galtung 1969, pp. 167–168, 183.

  122. 122.

    Ibid., p. 183.

  123. 123.

    On the interplay of cultural, structural and direct violence, see Galtung 2013a, p. 46; for the discussion of deep culture, see p. 56.

  124. 124.

    Roy 1999, as quoted in Nixon 2011, p. 1.

References

  • Anghie A, Chimni BS (2004) Third World Approaches to International Law and Individual Responsibility in Internal Conflict. Studies in Transnational Legal Policy 36: 185–210

    Google Scholar 

  • Antiphon (2009) Power, Violence, Law. Critical Legal Thinking. https://criticallegalthinking.com/2009/04/05/power-violence-law/. Accessed 14 May 2021

  • Baars G (2019) The Corporation, Law and Capitalism: A Radical Perspective on the Role of Law in the Global Political Economy. Brill Nijhoff, Leiden/Boston

    Google Scholar 

  • Bassiouni MC (2013) Introduction to International Criminal Law, 2nd rev. edn. Martinus Nijhoff, Leiden/Boston

    Google Scholar 

  • Burgis-Kasthala M (2014) An Arresting Event: Assassination within the Purview of International Criminal Law. In: Schwöbel C (ed) Critical Approaches to International Criminal Law. Routledge, London/New York, pp 245–263

    Google Scholar 

  • Butler J (2009) Frames of War: When Is Life Grievable? Verso, London/New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Carvalho H (2019) The Violence of Criminalisation. ISRF Bulletin XX: 9–12

    Google Scholar 

  • Cassese A (2008) International Criminal Law, 2nd edn. Oxford University Press, Oxford/New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Cox RW (1981) Social Forces, States and World Orders: Beyond International Relations Theory. Millennium 10: 126–155

    Google Scholar 

  • Cox RW (1983) Gramsci, Hegemony and International Relations: An Essay in Method. Millennium 12: 162–175

    Google Scholar 

  • Cryer R (2010) An Introduction to International Criminal Law and Procedure. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Cutler AC (2005) Gramsci, Law, and the Culture of Global Capitalism. Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy. 8: 527–542

    Google Scholar 

  • deGuzman MM (2020) Shocking the Conscience of Humanity: Gravity and the Legitimacy of International Criminal Law. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Duff RA (2007) Answering for Crime: Responsibility and Liability in the Criminal Law. Hart, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Esenin S (undated) Letter to a Woman. https://ruverses.com/sergey-esenin/letter-to-a-woman/6693/. Accessed 24 August 2021

  • Farmer P (2003) Pathologies of Power: Health, Human Rights, and the New War on the Poor. University of California Press, Berkeley

    Google Scholar 

  • Galtung J (1969) Violence, Peace, and Peace Research. Journal of Peace Research 6: 167–191

    Google Scholar 

  • Galtung J (2013a) Cultural Violence. In: Galtung J, Fischer D (eds) Johan Galtung: Pioneer of Peace Research. Springer, Berlin/Heidelberg, pp 41–58

    Google Scholar 

  • Galtung J (2013b) Violence: Direct, Structural and Cultural. In: Galtung J, Fischer D (eds) Johan Galtung: Pioneer of Peace Research. Springer, Berlin/Heidelberg, pp 35–40

    Google Scholar 

  • Gevers C (2014) International Criminal Law and Individualism: An African Perspective. In: Schwöbel C (ed) Critical Approaches to International Criminal Law. Routledge, London/New York, pp 221–245

    Google Scholar 

  • Gramsci A (2007) Prison Notebooks, Volume 3. Columbia University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Guilfoyle D (2020) Transnational Crimes. In: Heller K et al. (eds) The Oxford Handbook of International Criminal Law. Oxford University Press, Oxford/New York, pp 791–810

    Google Scholar 

  • Humphreys S (2010) Theatre of the Rule of Law: Transnational Legal Intervention in Theory and Practice. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • International Criminal Court (2013) Elements of Crimes. https://www.icc-cpi.int/Publications/Elements-of-Crimes.pdf. Accessed 28 August 2021

  • Kalpouzos I, Mann I (2015) Banal Crimes against Humanity: The Case of Asylum Seekers in Greece. Melbourne Journal of International Law 15: 1–28

    Google Scholar 

  • Kendall S (2015) Commodifying Global Justice: Economies of Accountability at the International Criminal Court. Journal of International Criminal Justice 13: 113–134

    Google Scholar 

  • Knox R (2019) Hegemony. In: D’Aspremont J, Singh S (eds) Concepts for International Law: Contributions to Disciplinary Thought. Edward Elgar Publishing, Cheltenham, pp 329–360

    Google Scholar 

  • Krever T (2013) International Criminal Law: An Ideology Critique. Leiden Journal of International Law 26: 701–723

    Google Scholar 

  • Krever T (2014a) Dispensing Global Justice. New Left Review 85: 66–97

    Google Scholar 

  • Krever T (2014b) Unveiling (and Veiling) Politics in International Criminal Trials. In: Schwöbel C (ed) Critical Approaches to International Criminal Law: An Introduction. Routledge, London/New York, pp 117–137

    Google Scholar 

  • Marks S (2008) Introduction. In: Marks S (ed) International Law on the Left: Re-examining Marxist legacies. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 1–29

    Google Scholar 

  • Marks S (2011) Human Rights and Root Causes. Modern Law Review 74: 57–78

    Google Scholar 

  • McAuliffe P, Schwöbel-Patel C (2018) Disciplinary Matchmaking. Journal of International Criminal Justice 16: 985–1009

    Google Scholar 

  • Mégret F (2014) Introduction: Situating Critical Approaches to International Criminal Justice. In: Schwöbel C (ed) Critical Approaches to International Criminal Law: An Introduction. Routledge, London/New York, pp 17–53

    Google Scholar 

  • Mégret F (2015) What Sort of Global Justice Is “International Criminal Justice”? Journal of International Criminal Justice 13: 77–96

    Google Scholar 

  • Mégret F (2020) The Unity of International Criminal Law: A Socio-Legal View. In: Heller K et al. (eds) The Oxford Handbook of International Criminal Law. Oxford University Press, Oxford/New York, pp 811–838

    Google Scholar 

  • Miéville C (2005) Between Equal Rights: A Marxist Theory of International Law. Brill, Leiden

    Google Scholar 

  • Moreno-Ocampo L (2007) International Criminal Court: Seeking Global Justice. Case Western Reserve Journal of International Law 40: 215–226

    Google Scholar 

  • Morton AD (2007) Unravelling Gramsci: Hegemony and Passive Revolution in the Global Political Economy. Pluto Press, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Nielsen C (2008) From Nuremberg to the Hague: The Civilizing Mission of International Criminal Law. Auckland University Law Review 14: 81–114

    Google Scholar 

  • Nixon R (2011) Slow Violence and the Environmentalism of the Poor. Harvard University Press, Cambridge/London

    Google Scholar 

  • Nouwen SMH (2012) Justifying Justice. In: Crawford J, Koskenniemi M (eds) The Cambridge Companion to International Law. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 327–51

    Google Scholar 

  • Nouwen SMH, Werner WG (2010) Doing Justice to the Political: The International Criminal Court in Uganda and Sudan. European Journal of International Law 21: 941–965

    Google Scholar 

  • Nouwen SMH, Werner WG (2015) Monopolizing Global Justice: International Criminal Law as Challenge to Human Diversity. Journal of International Criminal Justice 13: 157–176

    Google Scholar 

  • Office of the Prosecutor (2021) ICC Prosecutor, Fatou Bensouda, Meets with the EU Foreign Affairs Ministers: “The ICC Is Central to a More Just and Rules-Based International System”. https://www.icc-cpi.int/Pages/item.aspx?name=pr1569. Accessed 12 May 2021

  • O’Keefe R (2015) International Criminal Law, 1st edn. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Parmentier S (2003) Global Justice in the Aftermath of Mass Violence. The Role of the International Criminal Court in Dealing with Political Crimes. International Annals of Criminology 41: 203–224

    Google Scholar 

  • Poulantzas N (1980) State, Power, Socialism. Verso, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Rajkovic NM (2020) What Is a “Grave” International Crime? The Rome Statute, Durkheim and the Sociology of Ruling Outrages. Loyola University Chicago International Law Review 16: 65–86

    Google Scholar 

  • Ratner SR (2015) The Thin Justice of International Law: A Moral Reckoning of the Law of Nations. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Roy A (1999) The Cost of Living. Modern Library, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Royer C (2017) International Criminal Justice Between Scylla and Charybdis—the “Peace Versus Justice” Dilemma Analysed Through the Lenses of Judith Shklar’s and Hannah Arendt’s Legal and Political Theories. Human Rights Review 18: 395–416

    Google Scholar 

  • Schabas W (2017) An Introduction to the International Criminal Court, 5th edn. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Schwöbel-Patel C (2020) The Core Crimes of International Criminal Law. In: Heller K et al. (eds) The Oxford Handbook of International Criminal Law. Oxford University Press, Oxford/New York, pp 768–790

    Google Scholar 

  • Schwöbel-Patel C (2021) Marketing Global Justice: The Political Economy of International Criminal Law. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Simpson G (2014) Linear Law: The History of International Criminal Law. In: Schwöbel C (ed) Critical Approaches to International Criminal Law: An Introduction. Routledge, London/New York, pp 159–179

    Google Scholar 

  • Tallgren I (2002) The Sensibility and Sense of International Criminal Law. European Journal of International Law 13: 561–595

    Google Scholar 

  • Tallgren I (2014) Who Are “We” in International Criminal Law? On Critics and Membership. In: Schwöbel C (ed) Critical Approaches to International Criminal Law: An Introduction. Routledge, London/New York, pp 71–95

    Google Scholar 

  • Torrens SM (2020) The Politics of International Criminal Justice: Hegemony and Humanity at the International Criminal Tribunal for the Former Yugoslavia. In: Cullen H et al. (eds) The Politics of International Criminal Law. Brill Nijhoff, Leiden/Boston, pp 56–84

    Google Scholar 

  • Tzouvala N (2020) Capitalism as Civilisation: A History of International Law. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Weigend T (2008) Societas Delinquere Non Potest? A German Perspective. Journal of International Criminal Justice 6: 927–945

    Google Scholar 

  • Wells C (2001) Corporations and Criminal Responsibility, 2nd edn. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Werle G (2007) Individual Criminal Responsibility in Article 25 ICC Statute. Journal of International Criminal Justice 5: 953–975

    Google Scholar 

  • Werle G, Jessberger F (2020) Principles of International Criminal Law, 4th edn. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Žižek S (2009) Violence: Six Sideways Reflections. Profile Books, London

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Anastasiya Kotova .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2023 T.M.C. Asser Press and the authors

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Kotova, A. (2023). Violence in International Criminal Law and Beyond. In: Jeßberger, F., Steinl, L., Mehta, K. (eds) International Criminal Law—A Counter-Hegemonic Project?. International Criminal Justice Series, vol 31. T.M.C. Asser Press, The Hague. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-6265-551-5_3

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-6265-551-5_3

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: T.M.C. Asser Press, The Hague

  • Print ISBN: 978-94-6265-550-8

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-6265-551-5

  • eBook Packages: Law and CriminologyLaw and Criminology (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics