Skip to main content

State Sovereignty, Cosmopolitanism and the International Criminal Court

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Defining International Terrorism

Part of the book series: International Criminal Justice Series ((ICJS,volume 15))

Abstract

The overarching argument of this book is that a definition of international terrorism in an international criminal law context will not be functional nor serve the purposes of international criminal justice unless it balances properly State sovereignty considerations and cosmopolitan ideals. The State-centric theory of international law on the one hand, and cosmopolitanism on the other, treat the concept of State sovereignty from different perspectives, with the former emphasising sovereign interests , sometimes at the expense of international criminal justice purposes, and the latter prioritising cosmopolitan aspirations over the respect for State sovereignty. The crime of aggression and international terrorism present aspects that can be addressed in either a pro-State sovereignty or a pro-cosmopolitan context. This chapter will focus at this differentiation of the treatment of State sovereignty in the context of the UN Charter and the Rome Statute frameworks, focusing on the regime of complementarity enshrined in the latter and contributing thus to our understanding of the differentiated approaches that the Security Council and the ICC follow on issues that touch upon State sovereignty. The effectiveness of the definitions of international crimes as provided into the Rome Statute, and for the purposes of this book, the definition of the crime of aggression and possibly terrorism, will ultimately be determined by whether they will be successful in promoting the cosmopolitan ethos that the ICC represents in an international system of sovereign States which might feel threatened by that ethos.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 99.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Charter of the United Nations, opened for signature 26 June 1945, 1 UNTS XVI (entered into force 24 October 1945) (UN Charter).

  2. 2.

    UNGA 1998.

  3. 3.

    Rome Statute of the International Criminal Court, opened for signature 17 July 1998, 2187 UNTS 90 (entered into force 1 July 2002) UN Doc. A/CONF. 183/9 (Rome Statute).

  4. 4.

    The conditions of inadmissibility of a case as provided by Article 17(1) of the Rome Statute are: ‘(a) The case is being investigated or prosecuted by a State which has jurisdiction over it, unless the State is unwilling or unable genuinely to carry out the investigation or prosecution; (b) The case has been investigated by a State which has jurisdiction over it and the State has decided not to prosecute the person concerned, unless the decision resulted from the unwillingness or inability of the State genuinely to prosecute; …’.

  5. 5.

    Kelsen 19591960, p. 627.

  6. 6.

    For an elaboration on the concept of sovereignty and its historical development see Henley 2011, pp. 1025–1027.

  7. 7.

    This is also in accord with Kelsen ’s monistic theory, where he argues that ‘international law and national law form a unity’ which can be achieved with the primacy of the one over the other (Kelsen 19591960, p. 629). See also text to n. 78.

  8. 8.

    Ibid., 630.

  9. 9.

    Brus 2002, p. 3.

  10. 10.

    Mégret 2001, p. 257.

  11. 11.

    Jennings 2002, p. 27.

  12. 12.

    Kelsen 19591960, p. 627.

  13. 13.

    Broomhall 2003, p. 56 commenting on Cassese 1998, pp. 11–17.

  14. 14.

    Jennings 2002, p. 29.

  15. 15.

    UN Charter, above n. 1, Preamble. See also Articles 1(2) and 55.

  16. 16.

    Nagan and Hammer 2004, p. 171. While the principle of national self-determination as a manifestation of the sovereignty of the people was asserted from the French revolution, it lost ground during the Cold War era but regained its validity after the demise of the bi-polar model of balance of power (in Pavković and Radan 2003, p. 4).

  17. 17.

    That a State exercises public powers within a territory does not necessarily mean that these powers are sovereign if this happens contrary to the will of the people. In this case, one can talk about violation of the sovereignty of the people. See also Sarooshi 2005, pp. 9–10.

  18. 18.

    Broomhall 2003, p. 52.

  19. 19.

    Cabrera 2011, p. 209.

  20. 20.

    Brown 2005, pp. 497–98.

  21. 21.

    Ibid., p. 501.

  22. 22.

    Kant 1793 in Reiss 1970, pp. 61–92.

  23. 23.

    Gregor 1996, p. 96.

  24. 24.

    Brown 2005, p. 501.

  25. 25.

    Teson 1992, pp. 86–7.

  26. 26.

    Cheah 2006, p. 486.

  27. 27.

    Zolo 1999, p. 437; Zolo 1998, p. 310.

  28. 28.

    Pogge 1992, p. 58.

  29. 29.

    Ibid.

  30. 30.

    Ibid., pp. 61–62.

  31. 31.

    Wacks 2005 in Fouladvand 2012, p. 30.

  32. 32.

    Archibugi 1995, p. 443.

  33. 33.

    Finch 1979, p. 37.

  34. 34.

    Koller 2008, p. 1050.

  35. 35.

    Archibugi 1995, p. 443.

  36. 36.

    Fouladvand 2012, p. 40.

  37. 37.

    Feldman 2007, p. 1045.

  38. 38.

    Rome Statute, above n. 3, Preamble paras 2 and 4.

  39. 39.

    Feldman 2007, pp. 1065–1069.

  40. 40.

    Ibid., p. 1067.

  41. 41.

    Kelsen 19591960, p. 636.

  42. 42.

    Ibid. However, it is obvious that these two types of sovereignty, the absolute supremacy of national order and the unlimited competence of a State to act (inside or outside its territory) are two sides of the same coin. What Kelsen is trying to argue with this distinction is that, although the absolutist view about sovereignty is in any respect antithetical to international law, a State’s freedom of action is not, if conditioned upon certain rules.

  43. 43.

    Ibid., p. 637.

  44. 44.

    UN Charter, above n. 1, Article 3.

  45. 45.

    Ibid., Article 2(7): ‘Nothing contained in the present Charter shall authorize the United Nations to intervene in matters which are essentially within the domestic jurisdiction of any state or shall require the Members to submit such matters to settlement under the present Charter; but this principle shall not prejudice the application of enforcement measures under Chapter VII.’

  46. 46.

    Nagan and Hammer 2004, p. 25.

  47. 47.

    UN Charter, above n. 1, Article 2(4).

  48. 48.

    Ibid., Article 1.

  49. 49.

    Ibid., Article 4.

  50. 50.

    Ibid., Article 10.

  51. 51.

    Nagan and Hammer 2004, p. 26; Goodrich and ors 1969, pp. 290–309.

  52. 52.

    UN Charter, above n. 1, Article 27(3). The power of veto is not explicitly mentioned in the UN Charter, however Article 27(3) requires the concurring votes of the five permanent members of the Security Council for the adoption of resolutions that concern non-procedural matters (regulated by Article 27(2)), permitting thus any permanent Member to block the proceedings.

  53. 53.

    Ibid., Article 42.

  54. 54.

    Ibid., Article 24.

  55. 55.

    Ibid., Article 39.

  56. 56.

    UN Charter, above n. 1, Article 24(2): ‘In discharging these duties [concerning its responsibility for the maintenance of international peace and security] the Security Council shall act in accordance with the Purposes and Principles of the United Nations…’. See also Kelsen 1950, pp. 294–95.

  57. 57.

    Brus 2002, p. 8.

  58. 58.

    Broomhall 2003, p. 58.

  59. 59.

    Ibid., p. 61.

  60. 60.

    Broomhall 2003, pp. 152–54. In the case of the ICTR, two incidents are worth noticing: in the first one, while the newly-formed Rwandan government invited the Security Council to establish the tribunal and engaged to cooperate, it then voted against the resolution adopting its Statute, on the basis of the temporal jurisdiction of the tribunal (post-genocide revenge killings by the Tutsis would fall into its jurisdiction) and of its failure to apply the death penalty. The second one involves an order of the ICTR Appeals Chamber to release a suspect whose rights of fair trial had been violated. In response, the Rwandan government promised to suspend its cooperation with the tribunal. The Prosecutor applied for a review of the decision for release and finally the Chamber reversed its initial decision. In the case of the ICTY, Croatia was mostly unwilling to extradite its nationals to the tribunal or to provide evidence. It finally agreed to surrender to the tribunal Tihomir Blaskić and Zlatko Aleksovski, after the US’s threats to block international loans. In the Report of the International Tribunal for the Prosecution of Persons Responsible for Serious Violations of International Humanitarian Law Committed in the Territory of the Former Yugoslavia since 1991 (1999), the ICTY stated that there was ‘a pattern of non-compliance, including the failure to defer to the competence of the Tribunal, failure to execute warrants, failure to provide evidence and information and the refusal to permit the Prosecutor and her investigators into Kosovo’, paras 91–99.

  61. 61.

    Rome Statute, above n. 3, Articles 86–102.

  62. 62.

    Broomhall 2003, p. 61.

  63. 63.

    It is more accurate to speak of a qualified or quasi-universal jurisdiction . Article 12(2) of the Rome Statute provides that the ICC may exercise its jurisdiction when the territorial State or the State of nationality of the accused (or both) are Parties to the Statute or have accepted its jurisdiction ad hoc. However, this jurisdictional link with the territorial or nationality State is not required in case of a Security Council referral of a situation to the ICC Prosecutor under Chapter VII of the UN Charter (Rome Statute, above n. 3, Articles 12 and 13). Besides, some of the crimes of the Rome Statute, such as the grave breaches of the Geneva Conventions (Rome Statute, above n. 3, Article 8(2a)), are subject to universal jurisdiction anyway. On the other hand, some national legislations relating to the implementation of the Rome Statute provisions either adopt the jurisdictional bases explicitly referred to in the Rome Statute or clearly establish universal jurisdiction. On national implementation of the Rome Statute substantive law see Kleffner 2003, p. 86.

  64. 64.

    Philippe 2006, p. 375, where he argues that the principle of complementarity is the means through which to enforce universal jurisdiction for international crimes.

  65. 65.

    As was also noted in Chap. 1, the international crimes under the ICC’s jurisdiction (genocide , war crimes , crimes against humanity and the crime of aggression) will be hereinafter referred to as Article 5 crimes .

  66. 66.

    Rome Statute, above n. 3, Article 17.

  67. 67.

    This third condition complements Article 20(3) of the Rome Statute, concerning the ne bis in idem principle.

  68. 68.

    Rome Statute, above n. 3, Article 17(1): ‘(a) The case is being investigated or prosecuted by a State which has jurisdiction over it, unless the State is unwilling or unable genuinely to carry out the investigation or prosecution; (b) The case has been investigated by a State which has jurisdiction over it and the State has decided not to prosecute the person concerned, unless the decision resulted from the unwillingness or inability of the State genuinely to prosecute;…’.

  69. 69.

    Rome Statute, above n. 3, Article 20(3).

  70. 70.

    Ibid., Article 17(2).

  71. 71.

    Ibid., Article 17(3).

  72. 72.

    Trahan 2012, pp. 581–82.

  73. 73.

    Ibid.

  74. 74.

    Ibid. See also Gurulé 20012002, p. 30.

  75. 75.

    Rome Statute, above n. 3, Article 17(2): ‘In order to determine unwillingness in a particular case, the Court shall consider, having regard to the principles of due process recognized by international law, whether one or more of the following exist, as applicable…’.

  76. 76.

    Benzing 2003, p. 613. According to Article 17(3) of the Rome Statute, inability is determined by three factors: whether, due to a total or substantial collapse or unavailability of its national judicial system the State is (i) unable to obtain the accused, (ii) unable to obtain the necessary evidence and testimony or (iii) otherwise unable to carry out its proceedings. In the ICC, Prosecutor v Saif Al-Islam Gaddafi and Abdullah Al-Senussi, Decision on the admissibility of a case against Saif Al-Islam Gaddafi, 31 May 2013, Case No. ICC-01/11-01/11-344-Conf (Gaddafi Admissibility Decision) para 200, the Pre-Trial Chamber held that the ability of a State to genuinely carry out proceedings ‘must be assessed in the context of the relevant national system and procedures… [and] in accordance with the substantive and procedural criminal law applicable in Libya’.

  77. 77.

    Rome Statute, above n. 3, Article 17(3).

  78. 78.

    The relationship between national and international legal orders has been divided into three, principal theories: (i) the monistic view which advocates the supremacy of national law over the international, (ii) the dualistic view which advocate that international law and national law are ‘independent of each other in their validity’ (Kelsen 19591960, p. 629) and therefore can be valid simultaneously and (iii) the monistic view which places international law above the various national legal systems. The dualistic theory started to lose ground after the second half of the 20th century and in its place, the monistic theory of international law supremacy over national legal systems started to emerge. The Vienna Convention on the Law of Treaties, (opened for signature 23 May 1969, 1155 UNTS 331, entered into force 27 January 1980) under Article 27, provides that a State party to a treaty cannot invoke national legislation as justification for non-compliance with its treaty obligations. Also, Article 88 of the Rome Statute provides that the national legal systems of its States Parties shall have in place procedures which allow all forms of cooperation, as envisaged by Part 9 of the Rome Statute, for the purposes of the ICC. The incorporation in domestic legislations of international rules as such is also another manifestation of the monistic theory of the primacy of international law over national legal orders. For a thorough analysis of these theories see Cassese 2005, pp. 213–237.

  79. 79.

    Benzing 2003, p. 614.

  80. 80.

    Doherty and McCormack 1999, p. 152; Kleffner 2003, p. 89. However, Colombia opposed to this interpretation. See also Declaration of Colombia upon ratification of the Rome Statute (1998) that ‘the word “otherwise” […] refers to the obvious absence of objective conditions necessary to the conduct of trial’ and that ‘none of the provisions of the Rome Statute alters the domestic law applied by the Colombian judicial authorities in exercise of their domestic jurisdiction within the territory of the Republic of Colombia’.

  81. 81.

    Ibid.

  82. 82.

    Kleffner 2003, p. 95. In the Gaddafi Admissibility Decision, above n. 76, para 88, the Pre-Trial Chamber held that domestic prosecutions under the category of ordinary crimes can be considered sufficient provided though that the case covers the same conduct as the one to be charged by the ICC Prosecutor. A discussion on the ‘same person, same conduct’ test as has been applied by the ICC will follow in the next section.

  83. 83.

    McAuliffe 2014, p. 273; Robinson 2010, p. 96.

  84. 84.

    Benzing 2003, p. 616.

  85. 85.

    Rome Statute, above n. 3, Preamble paras 4, 6.

  86. 86.

    Kleffner 2003, p. 93.

  87. 87.

    Ibid.

  88. 88.

    Ibid., p. 94.

  89. 89.

    Newton 2011, p. 320.

  90. 90.

    International Criminal Court Act 2001 c 17.

  91. 91.

    Newton 2011, p. 321.

  92. 92.

    As was the case with ICC, Prosecutor v Thomas Lubanga Dyilo, Case No. ICC-01/04-01/06-8, which will be commented below.

  93. 93.

    Hirondelle News Agency 2008.

  94. 94.

    Article 259(1bis) of the Swiss Criminal Code, 21 December 1937 (status as of 1 May 2013) provides that public provocation to commit genocide is prosecutable only when genocide has taken place in whole or in part in Switzerland without criminalising incitement to commit genocide abroad. Also Article 264k(1) provides that a superior could be held responsible only for crimes he was aware that a subordinate has committed or will commit and failed to act. The Rome Statute establishes liability for superiors also in cases where a superior ‘should have known’ that the forces under his or her command have committed or will commit Article 5 crimes (Article 28(a)(i)).

  95. 95.

    Report of International Federation of Human Rights 2006.

  96. 96.

    Law on the Establishment of Extraordinary Chambers in the Courts of Cambodia for the Prosecution of Crimes Committed during the period of Democratic Kampuchea, 10 August 2001, amended 27 October 2004 (2001 Law).

  97. 97.

    The chapeau of the definition of crimes against humanity (Article 5 of 2001 Law) is taken from the UNSC 1994, Article 3.

  98. 98.

    Report of International Federation of Human Rights 2006, p. 21. Article 5 of the 2001 Law, above n. 96, omits some material acts included in Article 7 of the Rome Statute, above n. 3: enforced disappearances, sexual violence other than rape and the crime of apartheid.

  99. 99.

    Ibid. Article 5(2) of 2001 Law, above n. 96, includes extermination, enslavement, deportation, persecutions and other inhumane acts as constitutive elements of crimes against humanity without any definition of these terms. The crime of torture is defined, not according to Article 7 of the Rome Statute, above n. 3, but according to Article 500 of the 1955 Cambodian Criminal Code (Article 3 of the 2001 Law, above n. 96).

  100. 100.

    Mégret 2011, p. 363.

  101. 101.

    Ibid.

  102. 102.

    Rome Statute, above n. 3, Preamble.

  103. 103.

    Kleffner 2003, p. 93.

  104. 104.

    Rome Statute, above n. 3, Preamble para 4.

  105. 105.

    Benzing 2003, p. 603.

  106. 106.

    ICC, Situations under investigation 2017.

  107. 107.

    McAuliffe 2013, p. 215.

  108. 108.

    Mégret 2011, p. 376.

  109. 109.

    Ibid.

  110. 110.

    McAuliffe 2013, p. 215.

  111. 111.

    ICC, Prosecutor v Thomas Lubanga Dyilo, Under Seal Decision of the Prosecutor's Application for a Warrant of Arrest, Article 58, 10 February 2006, Case No. ICC-01/04-01/06-8 (Lubanga decision) paras 35–37.

  112. 112.

    Ibid., para 33.

  113. 113.

    Ibid., para 38.

  114. 114.

    Ibid., para 34.

  115. 115.

    Ibid., para 37.

  116. 116.

    Ibid., para 39.

  117. 117.

    Ibid., para 29.

  118. 118.

    Schabas 2008a, p. 757.

  119. 119.

    Jurdi 2011, p. 264.

  120. 120.

    Schabas 2008b, pp. 32–33.

  121. 121.

    McAuliffe 2013, pp. 220–21.

  122. 122.

    Schabas 2008a, p. 743.

  123. 123.

    ICC, Prosecutor v Germain Katanga, Case No. ICC-01/04-01/07-4.

  124. 124.

    ICC, Prosecutor v Germain Katanga, Decision on the Evidence and Information Provided by the Prosecution for the Issuance of a Warrant of Arrest for Germain Katanga, 6 July 2006, Case No. ICC-01/04-01/07-4, paras 3, 10.

  125. 125.

    Ibid., para 18.

  126. 126.

    ICC, Prosecutor v Germain Katanga and Mathieu Ngudjolo Chui, Motion Challenging the Admissibility of the Case by the Defence of Germain Katanga, pursuant to Article 19(2)(a) of the Statute, 11 March 2009, Case No. ICC-01/04-01/07-949 paras 31–37.

  127. 127.

    ICC, Prosecutor v Germain Katanga and Mathieu Ngudjolo Chui, Reasons for the Oral Decision on the Motion Challenging the Admissibility of the Case, 16 June 2009, Case No. ICC-01/04-01/07, para 77.

  128. 128.

    On how international institutions practically function in a privileging way towards State sovereignty see Kahn 2000, p. 10.

  129. 129.

    Nouwen 2011, pp. 212–214.

  130. 130.

    Schabas 2011, p. 156. However, he notes further that this over-intrusiveness was rather welcome by the DRC since prosecutions were targeted against enemies of the official government. In this respect see also Schabas 2010; Tiemessen 2014, p. 444.

  131. 131.

    Mégret 2006, pp. 49–51.

  132. 132.

    Rome Statute, above n. 3, Article 17.

  133. 133.

    Rome Statute, above n. 3, Article 12(2): ‘[…] (a) The State on the territory of which the conduct in question occurred or, if the crime was committed on board a vessel or aircraft, the State of registration of that vessel or aircraft; (b) The State of which the person accused of the crime is a national.’

  134. 134.

    Princeton Project on Universal Jurisdiction 2001, Principle 2(1).

  135. 135.

    Dinstein 2005, p. 145; Brotóns 2005, p. 16 quoted in Wrange 2010, p. 600.

  136. 136.

    International Law Commission 1996, Article 8: ‘…Jurisdiction over the crime set out in Article 16 shall rest with an international court. However, a State referred to in Article 16 is not precluded from trying its nationals for the crime set out in that article.’

  137. 137.

    Clark 2011, p. 726.

  138. 138.

    Scharf 2012, p. 364.

  139. 139.

    PCIJ, SS Lotus (France v Turkey), Judgment, 1927, PCIJ Series A No. 10.

  140. 140.

    Ibid., para 46.

  141. 141.

    Scharf 2012, p. 380.

  142. 142.

    Trahan 2012, p. 587.

  143. 143.

    For a discussion concerning over-zealous national prosecutions see Trahan 2012, pp. 594–601.

  144. 144.

    Mégret and Samson 2013, p. 573.

  145. 145.

    Ibid., p. 586. About Rome Statute’s safeguards concerning due process protection see Fry 2012.

  146. 146.

    Morris 2001, pp. 14–15.

  147. 147.

    Resolution RC/Res. 6, Annex I, Amendments to the Rome Statute of the International Criminal Court on the Crime of Aggression, 11 June 2010 (Kampala Resolution ) Article 8bis: ‘For the purpose of this Statute, “crime of aggression” means the planning, preparation, initiation or execution, by a person in a position effectively to exercise control over or to direct the political or military action of a State, of an act of aggression which, by its character , gravity and scale , constitutes a manifest violation of the Charter of the United Nations.’

  148. 148.

    Van Schaack 2012, p. 149.

  149. 149.

    UN Charter, above n. 1, Article 39: ‘The Security Council shall determine the existence of any threat to the peace , breach of the peace , or act of aggression …’.

  150. 150.

    Among the authors that are sceptical about the application of the complementarity regime to cases of aggression are: Trahan 2012; Wrange 2010; Van Schaack 2012.

  151. 151.

    Van Schaack 2012, p. 151.

  152. 152.

    Kampala Resolution , above n. 147, Article 15bis (6) and (8).

  153. 153.

    Rome Statute, above n. 3, Article 27.

  154. 154.

    Wrange 2010, p. 594; Mégret 2011, p. 383 where he argues that immunity laws might be a legitimate reason for non-prosecution on a horizontal plane and between States but not before an independent international institution. See also Rome Statute, above n. 3, Article 98(1) where it states that without a waiver of immunity by the State whose national is being accused, the Court cannot proceed with a request for surrender or assistance.

  155. 155.

    Broomhall 2003, p. 140. France and Germany have dealt with this issue by making amendments which either allow the surrender to the ICC but not the domestic prosecution of a person entitled to immunities (France) or allow both the surrender and prosecution after authorisation of the parliament (Germany).

  156. 156.

    Ibid., pp. 141–45.

  157. 157.

    As emphasised by Van Schaack, a national definition for aggression might for example reject the ‘leadership requirement ’ of the crime or the threshold of ‘manifest violation ’ or even permit the prosecution of ‘attempted aggression’, issues that have been decided upon after careful and rigorous negotiations by the ASP. Van Schaack 2012, p. 152.

  158. 158.

    Kampala Resolution , above n. 147, Annex III ‘Understandings regarding the amendments to the Rome Statute of the International Criminal Court on the crime of aggression’.

  159. 159.

    Van Schaack 2012, p. 155.

  160. 160.

    Ibid., p. 160.

  161. 161.

    Koh 2010.

  162. 162.

    Scharf 2012, p. 365.

  163. 163.

    Kress and von Holtzendorff 2010, p. 1216.

  164. 164.

    Van Schaack 2012, p. 161.

  165. 165.

    A thorough examination of the major points of contention on the core elements of an international definition for terrorism will follow in Chaps. 5 and 6.

References

  • Archibugi D (1995) Immanuel Kant, Cosmopolitan Law and Peace. EJIL 1(4): 429–456

    Google Scholar 

  • Benzing M (2003) The Complementarity Regime and the International Criminal Court: International Criminal Justice between State Sovereignty and the Fight Against Impunity. Max Planck Yrbk UN L 7: 591–632

    Google Scholar 

  • Broomhall B (2003) International Justice and the International Criminal Court: Between Sovereignty and the Rule of Law. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Brotóns AR (2005) Aggression, Crime of Aggression, Crime without Punishment. Working Paper No 10 (Fundación para las Relaciones Internacionales y el Diálogo Exterior (FRIDE): 1–17. http://fride.org/download/WP10_CrimeCastig_ENG_jun05.pdf. Accessed 3 February 2017

  • Brown GW (2005) State Sovereignty, Federation and Kantian Cosmopolitanism. Eur J Int Relat 11 (4): 495–522

    Google Scholar 

  • Brus M (2002) Bridging the Gap between State Sovereignty and International Governance: The Authority of Law. In: Kreijen G (ed) State, Sovereignty and International Governance. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 3–24

    Google Scholar 

  • Cabrera L (2011) Cosmopolitanism. In: Chatterjee DK (ed) Encyclopedia of Global Justice. Springer Science and Business Media B V, Dordrecht, p 209

    Google Scholar 

  • Cassese A (1998) On the Current Trends towards Criminal Prosecution and Punishment of Breaches of International Humanitarian Law. EJIL 9:2–17

    Google Scholar 

  • Cassese A (2005) International Law, 2nd edn. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Cheah P (2006) Cosmopolitanism. Theory, Culture & Society 23: 486–496

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark R (2011) Complementarity and the Crime of Aggression. In: Stahn C, El Zeidy M (eds) The International Criminal Court and Complementarity: From Theory to Practice, vol 1, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 721–744

    Google Scholar 

  • Declaration of Colombia upon ratification of the Rome Statute (1998). www.icrc.org/ihl/NORM/909EEAAE157FBD43412566E100542BDE?OpenDocument. Accessed 2 February 2017

  • Dinstein Y (2005) War, Aggression and Self-Defence, 4th edn. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Doherty KL, McCormack TLH (1999) “Complementarity” as a Catalyst for Comprehensive Domestic Penal Legislation. U C Davis J Int’l L & Pol’y 5: 147–180

    Google Scholar 

  • Feldman N (2007) Cosmopolitan Law? Yale L J 116: 1022–1070

    Google Scholar 

  • Finch JD (1979) Introduction to Legal Theory, Sweet & Maxwell, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Fouladvand S (2012) Complementarity and Cultural Sensitivity: Decision-Making by the ICC Prosecutor in relation to the Situations in the Darfur region of the Sudan and the Democratic Republic of the Congo (DRC). DPhil thesis, University of Sussex, 30. http://sro.sussex.ac.uk/38540/. Accessed 1 February 2017

  • Fry E (2012) Between Show Trials and Sham Prosecutions: The Rome Statute’s Potential Effect on Domestic Due Process Protections. Crim L F 23: 35–62

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodrich LM and ors (1969) Charter of the United Nations; commentary and documents, 3rd edn. Columbia University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Gregor MJ (1996) Kant: The Metaphysics of Morals. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Gurulé J (2001–2002) United States Opposition to the 1998 Rome Statute Establishing an International Criminal Court: Is the Court’s Jurisdiction Truly Complementary to National Jurisdictions? 35 Cornell Int’l L J 35: 1–45

    Google Scholar 

  • Henley K (2011) Sovereignty. In: Chatterjee DK (ed) Encyclopedia of Global Justice. Springer Science and Business Media B V, Dordrecht, pp 1025–1027

    Google Scholar 

  • Hirondelle News Agency (2008) Swiss prepares bill to harmonise laws with ICC. www.hirondellenews.com/fr/icc/320-collaboration-with-states/21877-en-en-090508-swissicc-swiss-prepares-bill-to-harmonise-laws-with-icc1092810928. Accessed 2 February 2017

  • ICC, Situations under investigation. www.icc-cpi.int/en_menus/icc/situations%20and%20cases/Pages/situations%20and%20cases.aspx. Accessed 1 February 2017

  • International Law Commission (1996) Draft Code of Crimes against the Peace and Security of Mankind. UN Doc. A/CN4/L532

    Google Scholar 

  • International Tribunal for the Former Yugoslavia (1999) Report of the International Tribunal for the Prosecution of Persons Responsible for Serious Violations of International Humanitarian Law Committed in the Territory of the Former Yugoslavia since 1991, UN Doc. A/54/187

    Google Scholar 

  • Jennings R (2002) Sovereignty and International Law. In: Kreijen G (ed) State, Sovereignty and International Governance. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 27–44

    Google Scholar 

  • Jurdi NN (2011) The International Criminal Court and National Courts: A Contentious Relationship. Routledge, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Kahn P (2000) Speaking Law to Power: Popular Sovereignty, Human Rights, and the New International Order. Chi J Int’l L 1: 1–18

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant I (1793) On the Common Saying: This May be True in Theory, but it does not Apply in Practice. In: Reiss HS (ed) (1970) Kant’s Political Writings. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 61–92

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelsen H (1950) The Law of the United Nations: A Critical Analysis of its Fundamental Problem. The Lawbook Exchange Ltd, New Jersey

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelsen H (1959–1960) Sovereignty and International Law. The Georgetown L J 48(4):627–640

    Google Scholar 

  • Kleffner J (2003) The Impact of Complementarity on National Implementation of Substantive Criminal Law. JICJ 1: 86–113

    Google Scholar 

  • Koh HH, Legal Adviser, US Department of State (2010) Statement at the Review Conference of the International Criminal Court. www.state.gov/s/l/releases/remarks/142665.htm. Accessed 9 August 2015

  • Koller D (2008) The Faith of the International Criminal Lawyer. 40 NYU Journal of International Law and Politics 40: 1019–1069

    Google Scholar 

  • Kress C, von Holtzendorff L (2010) The Kampala Compromise on the Crime of Aggression. JICJ 8: 1179–1217

    Google Scholar 

  • McAuliffe P (2013) Transitional Justice and Rule of Law Reconstruction. Routledge, London

    Google Scholar 

  • McAuliffe P (2014) From Watchdog to Workhorse: Explaining the Emergence of the ICC’s Burden-Sharing Policy as an Example of Creeping Cosmopolitanism. Chinese JIL 13: 259–296

    Google Scholar 

  • Mégret F (2001) Epilogue to an Endless Debate: The International Criminal Court’s Third Party Jurisdiction and the Looming Revolution of International Law. EJIL 12 (2): 247–268

    Google Scholar 

  • Mégret F (2006) Why Would States Want to Join the ICC? A Theoretical Exploration Based on the Legal Nature of Complementarity. In: Kleffner J, Kor G (eds) Complementary Views on Complementarity. TMC Asser Press, The Hague, pp 1–51

    Google Scholar 

  • Mégret F (2011) Too much of a good thing? Implementation and the uses of complementarity. In: Stahn C, El Zeidy M (eds) The International Criminal Court and Complementarity: From Theory to Practice, vol 1. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 361–390

    Google Scholar 

  • Mégret F, Samson MG (2013) Holding the Line on Complementarity in Libya: The Case for Tolerating Flawed Domestic Trials. JICJ 11: 571–589

    Google Scholar 

  • Morris M (2001) High Crimes and Misconceptions: The ICC and Non-Party States. Law & Contemp Probs 64(1): 13–66

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagan WP, Hammer C (2004) The Changing Character of Sovereignty in International Law and International Relations. Colum JIL 43: 141–187

    Google Scholar 

  • Newton MA (2011) The quest of constructive complementarity. In: Stahn C, El Zeidy M (eds) The International Criminal Court and Complementarity: From Theory to Practice, vol 1. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 304–340

    Google Scholar 

  • Nouwen S (2011) Fine-tuning Complementarity. In: Brown BS (ed) Research Handbook of International Criminal Law. Edward Elgar, Cheltenham, pp 206–231

    Google Scholar 

  • Pavković A, Radan P (2003) In Pursuit of Sovereignty and Self-Determination: Peoples, States and Secession in the International Order. Macquarie LJ 3: 1–12

    Google Scholar 

  • Philippe X (2006) The principles of universal jurisdiction and complementarity: how do the two principles intermesh? Int’l Rev Red Cross 88 (862): 375–398

    Google Scholar 

  • Pogge T (1992) Cosmopolitanism and Sovereignty. Ethics 103: 48–75

    Google Scholar 

  • Princeton Project on Universal Jurisdiction (2001) The Princeton Principles on Universal Jurisdiction.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reiss HS (ed) (1970) Kant: Political Writings. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Report of the International Federation for Human Rights (2006) International Criminal Court, Implementation of the Rome Statute in Cambodian Law. No 443/2

    Google Scholar 

  • Robinson D (2010) The Mysterious Mysteriousness of Complementarity. Crim L F 21(1): 67–102

    Google Scholar 

  • Sarooshi D (2005) International Organisation and their exercise of Sovereign Powers. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Schabas W (2008) “Complementarity in Practice”: Some Uncomplimentary Thoughts. Crim L F 19(1): 5–33

    Google Scholar 

  • Schabas W (2008) Prosecutorial Discretion v. Judicial Activism at the International Criminal Court. JICJ 6: 731–761

    Google Scholar 

  • Schabas W (2011) The Rise and Fall of Complementarity. In: Stahn C, El Zeidy M (eds) The International Criminal Court and Complementarity: From Theory to Practice, vol 1. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 150–164

    Google Scholar 

  • Schabas W (2012) The International Criminal Court: Struggling to Find its Way. In: Cassese A (ed) Realizing Utopia: The Future of International Law. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 250–260

    Google Scholar 

  • Scharf M (2012) Universal Jurisdiction and the Crime of Aggression. Harv Int’l L J 53(2): 357–389

    Google Scholar 

  • Teson FR (1992) The Kantian Theory of International Law. Colum L Rev 92: 53–102

    Google Scholar 

  • Tiemessen A (2014) The International Criminal Court and the Politics of Prosecution. The International Journal of Human Rights 18(4–5): 444–461

    Google Scholar 

  • Trahan J (2012) Is Complementarity the right approach for the International Criminal Court’s Crime of Aggression? 45 Cornell Int’l L J 45: 569–601

    Google Scholar 

  • UNGA (1998) Diplomatic Conference of Plenipotentiaries on the Establishment of an International Criminal Court. UN Doc. A/CONF 183/13

    Google Scholar 

  • UNSC (1994) Statute of the International Criminal Tribunal for Rwanda. UN Doc. S/RES/955

    Google Scholar 

  • van Schaack B (2012) Par in parem imperium non habet, Complementarity and the Crime of Aggression. JICJ 10: 133–164

    Google Scholar 

  • Wacks R (2005) Understanding Jurisprudence: An Introduction to Legal Theory. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Wrange P (2010) The Crime of Aggression and Complementarity. In: Bellelli R (ed) International Criminal Justice: Law and Practice from the Rome Statute to Its Review. Ashgate, Farnham, pp 591–607

    Google Scholar 

  • Zolo D (1998) Hans Kelsen: International Peace through International Law. 9 EJIL 9: 306–324

    Google Scholar 

  • Zolo D (1999) A Cosmopolitan Philosophy of International Law? A Realist Approach. Ratio Juris 12(4): 429–444

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Stella Margariti .

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 T.M.C. Asser Press and the author

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Margariti, S. (2017). State Sovereignty, Cosmopolitanism and the International Criminal Court. In: Defining International Terrorism. International Criminal Justice Series, vol 15. T.M.C. Asser Press, The Hague. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-6265-204-0_2

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-6265-204-0_2

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: T.M.C. Asser Press, The Hague

  • Print ISBN: 978-94-6265-203-3

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-6265-204-0

  • eBook Packages: Law and CriminologyLaw and Criminology (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics