Skip to main content

Explanatory Interdependence: The Case of Stem Cell Reprogramming

  • Chapter
Explanation in Biology

Part of the book series: History, Philosophy and Theory of the Life Sciences ((HPTL,volume 11))

Abstract

Stem cells are defined as undifferentiated cells that can produce both undifferentiated and differentiated (specialized) cells. The stem cell concept is thus intimately connected to core assumptions about the process of development. Making these assumptions explicit clarifies the general explanandum-phenomenon of stem cell biology: the branching pattern of cell development, from a single initiating ‘stem,’ through intermediate stages, to one or more termini. Importantly, the whole process, not only developmental termini (specialized cells of a mature multicellular organism), is the target of explanation. Explanations of cell developmental processes are revealed by experiments. Here I focus on one important kind of experiment: direct cell reprogramming, which manipulates the development of cells in artificial culture conditions. I then examine three accounts of biological explanation in light of this case: interventionist, gene-centric, and mechanistic. Though each offers some insight into explanations based on reprogramming, none is fully satisfactory. This motivates a modified account of mechanistic explanation, emphasizing interdependence among components.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    E.g., Gottweis et al. (2009), Kraft (2009), Lau et al. (2008), and Maienschein et al. (2008).

  2. 2.

    For recent exceptions see Fagan (2013), Laplane (2011), and Leychkis et al. (2009).

  3. 3.

    A complementary view is offered by Gross (2015, this volume) who defends the explanatory value of non-dependence relationships.

  4. 4.

    Much about the process of development remains controversial, including its start- and end-points (see Pradeu 2011, and related articles).

  5. 5.

    Examples of such general definitions can be found in the most recent edition of Essentials of Stem Cell Biology (Melton and Cowan 2009, xxiv); the first issue of Cell Stem Cell, the official journal of the International Society for Stem Cell Research (Ramelho-Santos and Willenbring 2007, 35); and information pages on the websites of the US National Institutes of Health (http://stemcells.nih.gov/info/basics/basics1.asp) and the European Stem Cell Network (http://www.eurostemcell.org/stem-cell-glossary).

  6. 6.

    There are two modes of cell division: mitosis and meiosis. In mitosis, the genome replicates once before the cell divides. In meiosis, the genome replicates once, but two rounds of cell division follow, yielding four offspring cells with half the complement of DNA. Stem cell phenomena involve mitosis, so only that mode of cell division is discussed here.

  7. 7.

    Demonstrating this potential experimentally is another matter (see Fagan 2013).

  8. 8.

    Many stem cell biologists use calendar time rather than number of cell generations as a time-parameter. The two are interchangeable if an estimate of the rate of cell division for L is available (which is usually the case).

  9. 9.

    Another aspect of differentiation is diversification: a population of cells diversifies over n cell generations if and only if variation in C-values increases with successive generations. As the notion of specialization appears to predominate in stem cell research today, I focus on this aspect of differentiation.

  10. 10.

    The limiting case is an un-branched line. Some scientists deny that cells that initiate lineages with this pattern count as stem cells. This view imposes an additional constraint on the minimal model; the basic components and relations are the same.

  11. 11.

    For simplicity, I focus on explanations of a single cell’s development. In practice, however, cell populations are of equal importance (see Fagan 2013, Chap. 3).

  12. 12.

    The first two are ‘cloning’ techniques of the sort that produced Dolly the sheep. They are usually conceived as effects of cytoplasm on the nucleus, while the latter two are conceived as effects of external factors on whole cells.

  13. 13.

    Details in Takahashi and Yamanaka (2006), Takahashi et al. (2007)

  14. 14.

    Reviewed in Maherali and Hochedlinger (2008), Hochedlinger and Plath (2009), Stadtfeld and Hochedlinger (2010), Okita and Yamanaka (2011), and Robinton and Daley (2012).

  15. 15.

    The significance of Waddington’s landscape for stem cell biology, and interfield relations with systems biology are discussed further in Fagan (2012a, b, 2013).

  16. 16.

    Woodward’s full analysis is more elaborate. But this simplified treatment will do for present purposes.

  17. 17.

    Waters does allow that some molecules other than DNA qualify as actual specific difference-makers, notably RNA splicing agents and micro-RNAs in eukaryotes (2007, pers. comm.). So his view is not strictly gene-centric. Nonetheless, explanatory privilege for these other molecules is premised on their being causes of the same sort as DNA, and in this sense, Waters’ view is gene-centric. Thanks to the editors for pushing me to clarify this point.

  18. 18.

    Paraphrase of Waters (2007, 566–567). The final requirement is further explicated by several conditions pertaining to specificity, which are set aside here for simplicity.

  19. 19.

    Woodward distinguishes two specificity concepts. As they are closely related, however, I discuss only the more rigorous here.

  20. 20.

    Influential case studies include: Bechtel (2006), Darden (2006), and Craver (2007).

  21. 21.

    This terminology follows Machamer et al. (2000). There are several other important accounts of mechanistic explanation in biology, which overlap in many but not in all respects; these include Glennan (1996, 52) and Bechtel and Abrahamsen (2005, 423). Note that this definition is actually narrower than that of Machamer and colleagues, restricted to constitutive or multilevel mechanisms (see below).

  22. 22.

    Experimental biologists often seek underlying mechanisms, to explain an overall process in terms of its working parts. This is part of the explanatory aim shared by many stem cell biologists.

  23. 23.

    This formulation is not Woodward’s own, though it captures what I take to be the main ideas of conception of modularity as it pertains to mechanistic explanation. Modularity in Woodward’s own theory (2003) has a somewhat different significance.

  24. 24.

    This term is adapted from social action theory, where it describes actions of two or more agents (e.g., walking together, building a cathedral) and associated intentions.

  25. 25.

    For simplicity, only the two-component case is presented. This makes condition (ii) redundant though it is necessary for complexes with three or more components.

References

  • Bechtel, W. (2006). Discovering cell mechanisms. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W., & Abrahamson, A. (2005). Explanation: A mechanist alternative. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 36, 421–441.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brandt, C. (2010). The metaphor of ‘nuclear reprogramming’. In A. Barahona, E. Suarez-Díaz, & H.-J. Rheinberger (Eds.), The hereditary hourglass: Genetics and epigenetics, 1868–2000 (pp. 85–95). Berlin: Max Planck Institute for History of Science.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carroll, S. (2005). Endless forms most beautiful. New York: W.W. Norton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, D., & Melton, D. (2011). Turning straw into gold. Nature Reviews Genetics, 12, 243–252.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Craver, C. (2007). Explaining the brain. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Darden, L. (2006). Reasoning in biological discoveries. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Fagan, M. B. (2012a). Waddington redux: Models and explanation in stem cell and systems biology. Biology and Philosophy, 27, 179–213.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fagan, M. B. (2012b). Materia mathematica: Models in stem cell biology. Journal for Experimental and Theoretical Artificial Intelligence, 24, 315–327.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fagan, M. (2012c). The joint account of mechanistic explanation. Philosophy of Science, 79, 448–472.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fagan, M. (2013). Philosophy of stem cell biology. London: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Glennan, S. (1996). Mechanisms and the nature of causation. Erkenntnis, 44, 49–71.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gottweis, H., Salter, B., & Waldby, C. (2009). The global politics of human embryonic stem cell science. London: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gross, F. (2015). The relevance of irrelevance: Explanation in systems biology. In P.-A. Braillard & C. Malaterre (Eds.), Explanation in biology. An enquiry into the diversity of explanatory patterns in the life sciences (pp. 175–198). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hanna, J., Saha, K., Pando, B., van Zon, J., Lengner, C., Creyghton, M., van Oudenaarden, A., & Jaenisch, R. (2009). Direct cell reprogramming is a stochastic process amenable to acceleration. Nature, 462, 595–601.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hanna, J., Saha, K., & Jaenisch, R. (2010). Pluripotency and cellular reprogramming: Facts, hypotheses, unresolved issues. Cell, 143, 508–525.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hitchcock, C., & Woodward, J. (2003). Explanatory generalizations, Part II. Noûs, 37, 181–199.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hochedlinger, K., & Plath, K. (2009). Epigenetic reprogramming and induced pluripotency. Development, 136, 509–523.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kraft, A. (2009). Manhattan transfer: Lethal radiation, bone marrow transplantation, and the birth of stem cell biology, 1942–1961. Historical Studies in the Natural Sciences, 39, 171–218.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Laplane, L. (2011). Stem cells and the temporal boundaries of development: Toward a species-dependent view. Biological Theory, 6, 48–58.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lau, D., Ogbogu, U., Taylor, B., Stafinski, T., Menon, D., & Caulfield, T. (2008). Stem cell clinics online: The direct-to-consumer portrayal of stem cell medicine. Cell Stem Cell, 3, 591–594.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leychkis, Y., Munzer, S., & Richardson, J. (2009). What is stemness? Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 40, 312–320.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Machamer, P., Darden, L., & Craver, C. (2000). Thinking about mechanisms. Philosophy of Science, 67, 1–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maherali, N., & Hochedlinger, K. (2008). Guidelines and techniques for the generation of induced pluripotent stem cells. Cell Stem Cell, 3, 595–605.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maienschein, J., Sunderland, M., Ankeny, R., & Robert, J. (2008). The ethos and ethics of translational research. The American Journal of Bioethics, 8, 43–51.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Melton, D., & Cowan, C. (2009). Stemness: Definitions, criteria, and standards. In R. Lanza et al. (Eds.), Essentials of stem biology (2nd ed., pp. xxii–xxix). San Diego: Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nobel Foundation (2012) The 2012 Nobel prize in physiology or medicine – press release. Nobelprize.org. 10 Oct 2012, http://www.nobelprize.org/nobel_prizes/medicine/laureates/2012/press.html

  • Okita, K., & Yamanaka, S. (2011). Induced pluripotent stem cells: Opportunities and challenges. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society (London) Series B, 366, 2198–2207.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pradeu, T. (ed.) (2011). Biological theory. Special issue on ‘Limits of development.’ Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ramalho-Santos, M., & Willenbring, H. (2007). On the origin of the term ‘stem cell’. Cell Stem Cell, 1, 35–38.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Robinton, D., & Daley, G. (2012). The promise of induced pluripotent stem cells in research and therapy. Nature, 481, 295–305.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stadtfeld, M., & Hochedlinger, K. (2010). Induced pluripotency: History, mechanisms, and applications. Genes & Development, 24, 2239–2263.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Takahashi, K., & Yamanaka, S. (2006). Induction of pluripotent stem cells from mouse embryonic and adult fibroblast cultures by defined factors. Cell, 126, 663–676.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Takahashi, K., Tanabe, K., Ohnuki, M., Narita, M., Ichisaka, T., Tomoda, K., & Yamanaka, S. (2007). Induction of pluripotent stem cells from adult human fibroblasts by defined factors. Cell, 131, 861–872.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Waddington, C. H. (1957). The strategy of the genes. London: Taylor & Francis.

    Google Scholar 

  • Waters, C. K. (2007). Causes that make a difference. Journal of Philosophy, 104, 551–579.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, J. (2002). What is a mechanism? A counterfactual account. Philosophy of Science, 69, S366–S377.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, J. (2003). Making things happen. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, J. (2010). Causation in biology. Biology and Philosophy, 25, 287–318.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Yamanaka, S. (2007). Strategies and new developments in the generation of patient-specific pluripotent stem cells. Cell Stem Cell, 1, 39–49.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Yamanaka, S. (2009). Elite and stochastic models for induced pluripotent stem cell generation. Nature, 460, 49–52.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zhou, Q., & Melton, D. (2008). Extreme makeover. Cell Stem Cell, 3, 382–388.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Many thanks to Pierre-Alain Braillard and Christophe Malaterre for the opportunity to contribute to this volume as well as helpful comments on the manuscript. Earlier versions of material in this paper were presented at workshops on Epistemology of Modeling and Simulation (Pittsburgh, PA, April 2011), Interdisciplinarity and Systems Biology (Aarhus University, Denmark, August 2011), and Individuals Across the Sciences (Sorbonne, Paris, May 2012), and at meetings of the Society for the Philosophy of Science in Practice (Exeter, UK, June 2011) and the American Philosophical Association, Pacific Division (Seattle, WA, April 2012). This essay has benefited from questions and comments of participants at all these events. Particular thanks are due to Hanne Andersen, Richard Grandy, Oleg Igoshin, Kirstin Matthews, Sean Morrison, Maureen O’Malley, Joe Ulatowski, Irv Weissman, and participants in the Fall 2010 graduate seminar in Philosophy of Science (Rice University). Support for this research was provided by the Humanities Research Center at Rice University’s Collaborative Research Fellowship (2009–2010), and Faculty Innovation Fund (2010–2012).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Melinda Bonnie Fagan .

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2015 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Fagan, M.B. (2015). Explanatory Interdependence: The Case of Stem Cell Reprogramming. In: Explanation in Biology. History, Philosophy and Theory of the Life Sciences, vol 11. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-9822-8_17

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics