Skip to main content

DSM-5: The Delayed Demise of Descriptive Diagnosis

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
The DSM-5 in Perspective

Part of the book series: History, Philosophy and Theory of the Life Sciences ((HPTL,volume 10))

Abstract

In 1980, DSM-III adopted a descriptive approach to psychiatric diagnosis, creating checklists of unwanted behaviors to define and use as required criteria when posing each of several hundred diagnoses. The objective of this novel approach was to validate psychiatry as a scientifically legitimate branch of medicine, by enabling research into hopefully homogeneous groups of patients to pinpoint the implicit hypothesized physiological causes of the disorders the patients were presumably sharing. In each subsequent revision of the DSM including the DSM-5, however, no physiological criteria of any sort are included for any diagnosis, confirming the empirical failure of this attempt to substantiate the medical model of madness. The futile endeavor to validate countless human faults and suffering as medical diseases explains most of the “scientific” conundrums and controversies surrounding the release of DSM-5, including whether to include or exclude diagnoses, where to draw boundaries for each, and why clinicians still fail to agree on which diagnosis they should apply in a given case. Despite DSM-5’s insolvency, the essentially moral project of descriptive psychiatric diagnosis has today vast socio-economic ramifications that help to preserve it.

To appear in The DSM-5 in Perspective: Philosophical Reflections on the Psychiatric Babel, edited by Steeves Demazeux & Patrick Singy, in series History, Philosophy and Theory of the Life Sciences, Springer. Some parts of this chapter are adapted with permission from material in Mad Science: Psychiatric Coercion, Diagnosis, and Drugs, Transaction Publisher, 2013.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 139.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    If one counts DSM-III-R (1987) and DSM-IV-TR (2000), DSM-5 is the seventh edition.

  2. 2.

    This is a term of art with which we disagree and discuss in detail in Kirk et al. (2013).

  3. 3.

    As its predecessors, DSM-5 states in several places that probable or definitive biomarkers for mental disorders or illnesses are lacking. Nonetheless, it does includes as “mental disorders” a number of diagnoses—for dementias, for example—whose criteria include evidence for a specified pathophysiological condition known to cause the presenting problem. Despite psychiatry’s historical role in managing senile older adults and others with organic psychoses and with degenerative brain diseases, the presence of these diagnoses is scientifically intriguing, as not all physical conditions with spectra of presenting psychological problems (e.g., epilepsy, diabetes) are so treated in the manual. Moreover, throughout the descriptive text that follows the criteria for each diagnostic category, sub-sections titled “Diagnostic Markers” or “Risk and Prognostic Factors” are frequently included. The relevant sub-section for Obsessive-Compulsive Disorder, for example, states the following: “Familial transmission is due in part to genetic factors (e.g., a concordance rate of 0.57 for monozygotic vs. 0.22 for dizygotic twins). Dysfunction in the orbitofrontal cortex, anterior cingulate cortex, and striatum have been most strongly implicated” (APA 2013, p. 240). Since the DSM-5, like its predecessors, lists no references, these assertions (all questionable and publicly questioned in their assumptions, determinations, and interpretations) arguably constitute pseudo-scientific adornments.

  4. 4.

    The medical illness metaphor is a conceit in that it states as fact that which has not yet been scientifically validated, namely that the behaviors defined as symptoms of mental illnesses are caused by biological dysfunction. The assertion that mental illnesses are physical illnesses has the powerful advantage of borrowing the language and causal model of biological disease to buttress the reputation of psychiatry, while obscuring the absence of any accepted scientific evidence for that claim. The “common vocabulary” that the DSM provides is that of the assumption and statement of illness, backed by the biomedical-industrial complex. The justification that “the DSM at least provides a common vocabulary” ignores (or exploits) the power of language to conquer rhetorically what cannot be validated empirically.

  5. 5.

    Kappa is a chance-corrected measure of reliability, that is, inter-judge agreement or consistency. Kappa coefficients may range from 0.0 to 1.0, from no agreement to perfect agreement, respectively. The developers of DSM-III were the first to use kappa as a measure of diagnostic consistency. They considered kappa scores of .70 or higher to be satisfactory or good and those around .50 or lower to be no better than fair or poor (see Kirk and Kutchins 1992).

  6. 6.

    Frances (2012a) writes that “mental disorders are constructs, nothing more but also nothing less. Schizophrenia is certainly not a disease; but equally it is not a myth. As a construct, schizophrenia is useful for purposes of communication and helpful in prediction and decision making — even if … the term has only descriptive, and not explanatory, power.”

  7. 7.

    A sample of these critics from various disciplines would include Boyle (2002), Dumont (1984), Eysenck (1986), Kirk and Kutchins (1992), Maj (2005), Mirowsky and Ross (1989), Mishara (1994), Sadler et al. (1994), Sarbin (1997), Szasz (1994), Tucker (1998), and Wakefield (1992).

  8. 8.

    Grass roots’ groups are not always genuinely grass roots. For example, the National Alliance on Mental Illness (NAMI), the principal “grass roots” mental health organization in America with a commitment to biological views regarding mental illness, receives between 60 % and 75 % of its annual budget from drug companies (see Kirk et al. 2013, pp. 16–17).

References

  • American Counseling Association. (2012). Retrieved on April 30, 2012, from http://www.counseling.org/PressRoom/NewsReleases.aspx?AGuid=315a280b-4d0b-48af-9421-1f7d3f01b4b7

  • American Psychiatric Association. (1980). Diagnostic and statistical manual of mental disorders, third edition (DSM-III). Washington, DC: American Psychiatric Association.

    Google Scholar 

  • American Psychiatric Association. (1987). Diagnostic and statistical manual of mental disorders, third edition-revised (DSM-III-R). Washington, DC: American Psychiatric Association.

    Google Scholar 

  • American Psychiatric Association. (1994). Diagnostic and statistical manual of mental disorders, fourth edition (DSM-IV). Washington, DC: American Psychiatric Association.

    Google Scholar 

  • American Psychiatric Association. (2000). Diagnostic and statistical manual of mental disorders, fourth edition (DSM-IV-TR). Washington, DC: American Psychiatric Association.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • American Psychiatric Association. (2013). Diagnostic and statistical manual of mental disorders, fifth edition (DSM-5). Washington, DC: American Psychiatric Association.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Angell, M. (2004). The truth about the drug companies: How they deceive us and what to do about it. New York: Random House.

    Google Scholar 

  • Angell, M. (2009). Drug companies & doctors: A story of corruption. The New York Review of Books, 56(1), 8–12.

    Google Scholar 

  • Angell, M. (2011). The epidemic of mental illness: Why? The New York Review of Books, 23 June.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barber, C. (2008). Comfortably numb: How psychiatry is medicating a nation. New York: Pantheon Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barglow, P. (2012, May/June). We can’t treat soldiers’ PTSD without a better diagnosis. Skeptical Inquirer, 36.3. Retrieved from http://www.csicop.org/si/show/we_cant_treat_soldiers_ptsd_without_a better diagnosis

  • Bayer, R. (1981). Homosexuality and American psychiatry: The politics of diagnosis. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Belluck, P. & Carey, B. (2013, May 7–13). Psychiatry’s new guide falls short, experts say. New York Times, p. A12.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bolton, D. (2008). What is mental disorder? An essay in philosophy, science, and values. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Boyle, M. (2002). Schizophrenia: A scientific delusion? (2nd ed.). East Sussex: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brauser, D. (2012). DSM-5 field trials generate mixed results. Medscape Medical News Psychiatry. Retrieved from www.medscape.com/viewarticle/763519?src=mpnews&spon=12

  • British Psychological Society (2011). Response to the American Psychiatric Association: DSM-5. Retrieved from http://www.bps.org.uk/news/psychologists-petition-against-dsm-5

  • Bruner, J. S., Goodnow, J. J., & Austin, G. A. (1986). A study of thinking. New Brunswick, NJ: Transaction.

    Google Scholar 

  • Caplan, P. (1995). They say you’re crazy: How the world’s most powerful psychiatrists decide who’s normal. Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carey, B. (2008, December 18). Psychiatrists revise the book of human troubles. New York Times.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carey, B. (2012a, January 24). Grief could join list of disorders. New York Times.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carey, B. (2012b, January 20). New definition of autism may exclude many, study suggests. New York Times.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carey, B. (2012c, March 29). Rate of autism diagnoses has climbed, study finds. New York Times.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, D. (2006). Critiques of the ADHD enterprise. In G. Lloyd, J. Stead, & D. Cohen (Eds.), Critical new perspectives on ADHD (pp. 137–155). London/New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cosgrove, L., & Krimsky, S. (2012). A comparison of DSM-IV and DSM-5 panel members’ financial association with industry: A pernicious problem persists. PLoS Medicine, 9(3), e1001190.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cosgrove, L., Krimsky, S., Vijayaraghavan, M., & Schneider, L. (2006). Financial ties between DSM-IV panel members and the pharmaceutical industry. Psychotherapy and Psychosomatics, 75, 154–160.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • DSM Task Force. (2012). Retrieved at http://www.DSM5.org/ProposedRevision/Pages/proposedrevision.aspx?rid=94. 30 Apr 2012.

  • Dumont, M. P. (1984). The non-specificity of mental illness. American Journal of Orthopsychiatry, 54, 326–335.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eysenck, H. J. (1986). A critique of contemporary classification and diagnosis. In T. Millon & G. L. Klerman (Eds.), Contemporary directions in psychopathology: Toward DSM-IV (pp. 73–98). New York: Guilford Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frances, A. (2009, June 26). A warning sign on the road to DSM-V: Beware of its unintended consequences. Psychiatric Times. http://www.psychiatrictimes.com/display/article/10168/1425378

  • Frances, A. (2010, June 2). Psychiatric fads and overdiagnosis. Psychology Today: DSM5 in Distress. http://www.psychologytoday.com/blog/dsm5-in-distress/201006/psychiatric-fads-and-overdiagnosis

  • Frances, A. (2012, March 16). Am I a dangerous man? Psychology Today: DSM5 in Distress. http://www.psychologytoday.com/blog/dsm5-in-distress/201203/am-i-dangerous-man

  • Frances, A. (2013a). Saving normal: An insider’s revolt against out-of-control psychiatric diagnosis, DSM-5, big pharma, and the medicalization of ordinary life. New York: HarperCollins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frances, A. (2013b, March 24). Letter to the New York Times, Sunday Review, p. 2.

    Google Scholar 

  • Francis, A. (2012a, August 8). A clinical reality check. Cato Unbound. http://www.cato-unbound.org/2012/08/08/allen-frances/clinical-reality-check

  • Friedman, R. (2013, May 21). The book stops here. New York Times, p. D3.

    Google Scholar 

  • Garner, D. (2013, May 2). Two pleas for sanity in judging saneness. New York Times, p. C1.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gomory, T., Cohen, D., & Kirk, S. (2013). Madness or mental illness? Revisiting historians of psychiatry. Current Psychology, 32(2), 119–135.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Graham, J. (2010, November 13). Doctors’ ties to drug industry still strong. Los Angeles Times.

    Google Scholar 

  • Greenberg, G. (2011, January). Inside the battle to define mental illness. Wired. http://www.wired.com/magazine/2010/12/ff_dsmv/

  • Grossman, R. (2008, December 29). Psychiatry manual’s secrecy criticized. Los Angeles Times.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harris, G. (2007, June 27). Psychiatrists top list in drug maker gifts. New York Times. http://www.nytimes.com/2007/06/27/health/psychology/27doctors.html

  • Harris, G. (2008a, November 21). Radio host has drug company ties. New York Times. http://www.nytimes.com/2008/11/22/health/22radio.html?em

  • Harris, G. (2008b, October 3). Top psychiatrist didn’t report drug makers’ pay. New York Times. http://www.nytimes.com/2008/10/04/health/policy/04drug.html?_r=1&oref=slogin

  • Harris, G., & Carey, B. (2008, June 8). Child experts fail to reveal full drug pay. New York Times. http://www.nytimes.com/2008/06/08/us/08conflict.html?pagewanted=all

  • Healy, D. (2012). Pharmageddon. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Healy, D., & Le Noury, J. (2007). Pediatric bipolar disorder: An object of study in the creation of an illness. International Journal of Risk and Safety in Medicine, 19, 209–221.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horwitz, A. V., & Wakefield, J. C. (2007). The loss of sadness: How psychiatry transformed normal sorrow into depressive disorder. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horwitz, A. V., & Wakefield, J. C. (2012). All we have to fear: Psychiatry’s transformation of natural anxieties into mental disorders. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hsieh, D. K., & Kirk, S. A. (2003). The effect of social context on psychiatrists’ judgments of adolescent antisocial behavior. Journal of Child Psychology and Psychiatry, 44(6), 877–887.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Insel, T. (2013). Director’s blog: Transforming diagnosis. Retrieved from http://www.nimh.nih.gov/about/director/2013/transforming-diagnosis.shtml

  • Jacobs, D. H., & Cohen, D. (2004). Hidden in plain sight: DSM-IV’s rejection of the categorical approach to diagnosis. Review of Existential Psychology and Psychiatry, 26, 81–96.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jacobs, D. H., & Cohen, D. (2010). Does “psychological dysfunction” mean anything? A critical essay on pathology versus agency. Journal of Humanistic Psychology, 50, 312–334.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jacobs, D. H., & Cohen, D. (2012). The end of neo-Kraepelinism. Ethical Human Psychology and Psychiatry, 14, 87–90.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jayson, S. (2013, May 13). Another go-around in the saga of psychiatry’s bible. USA Today, p. D4.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kirk, S. A., & Kutchins, H. (1992). The selling of DSM: The rhetoric of science in psychiatry. Hawthorne: Aldine de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kirk, S., Gomory, T., & Cohen, D. (2013). Mad science: Psychiatric coercion, diagnosis, and drugs. New Brunswick, NJ: Transaction Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klerman, G. (1978). The evolution of a scientific nosology. In J. C. Shershow (Ed.), Schizophrenia: Science and practice (pp. 99–119). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kraemer, H. C., Kupfer, D. J., Clarke, D. E., Narrow, W. E., & Regier, D. A. (2012). DSM-5: How reliable is reliable enough? American Journal of Psychiatry, 169(1), 13–15.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kupfer, D. (2013). Chair of DSM-5 task force discusses future of mental health research. Public statement, released May 6.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kupfer, D. J., First, M. B., & Regier, D. A. (2002). Introduction. In D. J. Kupfer, M. B. First, & D. A. Regier (Eds.), A research agenda for DSM-V (pp. xv–xxiii). Washington, DC: American Psychiatric Association.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kutchins, H., & Kirk, S. A. (1997). Making us crazy: DSM: The psychiatric bible and the creation of mental disorders. New York: Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lancet. (2012). Living with grief. Retrieved at: http://www.thelancet.com/journals/lancet/article/PIIS0140-6736(12)60248-7/fulltext

  • Lane, C. (2008, November 16). Wrangling over psychiatry’s bible. Los Angeles Times.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maj, M. (2005). Psychiatric comorbidity: An artifact of current diagnostic systems? British Journal of Psychiatry, 186, 182–184.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McNally, R. J. (2011). What is mental illness? Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mirowsky, J., & Ross, C. (1989). Psychiatric diagnosis as reified measurement. Journal of Health and Social Behavior, 30, 11–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mirowsky, J., & Ross, C. (1990). Subjective boundaries and combinations in psychiatric diagnosis. Journal of Mind and Behavior, 11, 407–420.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mishara, A. L. (1994). A phenomenological critique of commonsensical assumptions in DSM-III-R: The avoidance of the patient’s subjectivity. In J. Z. Sadler, M. A. Schwartz, & O. P. Wiggins (Eds.), Philosophical perspectives on psychiatric diagnostic classification. Baltimore: The Johns Hopkins University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • National Institute of Mental Health. (2008). Strategic planning reports. NIMH website, 15 Feb 2008.

    Google Scholar 

  • New York Times (Editorial). (2012, April 1). The puzzle of more autism cases.

    Google Scholar 

  • New York Times (Editorial). (2013, May 12). Shortcomings of a psychiatric bible. Sunday Review, p. 10.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nugent, B. (2012, January 31). I had Asperger syndrome. Briefly. New York Times.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rounsaville, B., Alcarcon, R., Andrews, G., Jackson, J. S., Kendell, R. E., & Kendler, K. (2002). Basic nomenclature issues for DSM-V. In D. J. Kupfer, M. B. First, & D. A. Regier (Eds.), A research agenda for DSM-V (pp. 1–29). Washington, DC: American Psychiatric Association.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sadler, J. Z., Hulgus, Y. F., & Agich, G. J. (1994). On values in recent American psychiatric classification. Journal of Medicine and Philosophy, 19, 261–277.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sarbin, T. R. (1997). On the futility of psychiatric diagnostic manuals (DSMs) and the return of personal agency. Applied and Preventive Psychology, 6, 233–243.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Satel, S. (2013, May 12). Why the fuss over the D.S.M.-5? New York Times, Sunday Review, p. 5.

    Google Scholar 

  • Society for Humanistic Psychology (2012). Retrieved April 30 2012 http://www.ipetitions.com/petition/DSM5/].

  • Spitzer, R. L. (2008). Psychiatrists revise diagnostic manual—In secret. Retrieved on Sept 25 2008 and posted at http://taxa.epi.umn.edu/~mbmiller/sscpnet/20080909 Spitzer/

  • Spitzer, R. L., Williams, J., & Endicott, J. (2012). Standards for DSM-5 reliability. American Journal of Psychiatry, 169(5), 537.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stein, D. J., Phillips, K. A., Bolton, D., Fulford, K. W. M., Sadler, J. Z., & Kendler, K. S. (2010). What is a mental/psychiatric disorder? From DSM-IV to DSM-V. Psychological Medicine, 40(11), 1759–1765.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Steinberg, P. (2012, January 31). Asperger’s history of over-diagnosis. New York Times.

    Google Scholar 

  • Szasz, T. (1961). The myth of mental illness: Foundations of a theory of personal conduct. New York: Hoeber-Harper.

    Google Scholar 

  • Szasz, T. (1994). Insanity: The idea and its consequences. New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tavris, C. (2013). How psychiatry went crazy. Wall Street Journal, May 18–19, pp. C5–C7.

    Google Scholar 

  • Torrey. (1970). The death of psychiatry. New York: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tucker, G. J. (1998). Putting DSM-IV in perspective. American Journal of Psychiatry, 155, 159–161.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wakefield, J. C. (1992). Disorder as harmful dysfunction: A conceptual critique of DSM-III-R’s definition of mental disorder. Psychological Review, 99, 232–247.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wakefield, J. C., & First, M. B. (2012). Validity of the bereavement exclusion to major depression: Does the empirical evidence support the proposal to eliminate the exclusion in DSM-5? World Psychiatry, 11, 3–10.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wang, S. (2013). Psychiatric manual’s role to narrow. Wall Street Journal, May 18–19, p. A3.

    Google Scholar 

  • Whitaker, R. (2010). Anatomy of an epidemic: Magic bullets, psychiatric drugs, and the astonishing rise of mental illness in America. New York: Crown.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, D. (2006, December 5). NIH scientist charged with conflict. Los Angeles Times.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, D. (2009, November 18). Medical schools quizzed on ghostwriting. New York Times. http://query.nytimes.com/gst/fullpage.html?res=9404EFDA173AF93BA25752C1A96F9C8B63&scp=1&sq=medical+schools+quizzed+on+ghostingwriting&st=nyt

  • Zarembo, A. (2011, December 11–16). Discovering autism (4 part series). Los Angeles Times.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Stuart A. Kirk .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2015 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Kirk, S.A., Cohen, D., Gomory, T. (2015). DSM-5: The Delayed Demise of Descriptive Diagnosis. In: Demazeux, S., Singy, P. (eds) The DSM-5 in Perspective. History, Philosophy and Theory of the Life Sciences, vol 10. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-9765-8_4

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics