Skip to main content

What Salamander Biologists Have Taught Us About Evo-devo

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Conceptual Change in Biology

Part of the book series: Boston Studies in the Philosophy and History of Science ((BSPS,volume 307))

Abstract

This chapter argues that historical and philosophical studies of David Wake’s 50-year investigation of the salamanders (Order Caudata) reveal a sustained effort to demonstrate the continuing value of taxon-centered research as opposed to or distinct from model organism research. Wake is an evolutionary morphologist involved in the emergence of Evo-devo and co-organizer of the 1981 Dahlem conference on Evolution and Development. He developed a distinctive practice of extrapolating “lessons” as well as results from his taxon-focused research on salamanders. Some of Wake’s contributions to the emergence and conceptual development of Evo-devo are characterized in terms of lessons learned from his use of the salamanders as a “model taxon.” Model taxa are intended to be monophyletic clades in which the whole clade constitutes the model, in contrast to model or experimental organisms, which are species used as models.

Isolated cases lack the impact that arises when one must confront the often conflicting lines of evidence that arise from a long-term focus on the evolution of a diverse monophyletic taxon (Wake 1991 , 544).

Taxon-based research in evolution permits…a multidimensional approach…with lessons learned from research on salamanders. The clade is widespread and diverse, yet sufficiently small that one can keep all of the species in mind. This facilitates research from diverse perspectives… (Wake 2009 , 333).

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 109.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 139.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    There is a terminological obstacle to discussing conceptual change in scientific “problems.” A problem can be something that poses a methodological or inferential difficulty or roadblock to the conduct of research. But a problem is also routinely described as a research or pedagogical question to be answered. Much of the philosophical and historical literature on scientific practice uses the term ‘problem’ to mean the latter—a research problem to be solved (e.g., Kuhn 1970; Laudan 1977). Wake et al. (2011) talk about “problems” in the former sense of methodological or inferential difficulty and use “question” to mean the latter sense. Here, I will use the term ‘difficulty’ to mean a “problem” of the former sort and use ‘problem’ to mean a research question.

  2. 2.

    Comparative morphology extends back as far as the ancient Greeks, but comparative methods and problems prior to the mid-nineteenth century are far beyond the scope of this essay.

  3. 3.

    In the case of salamanders, however, the diversity is ecological-functional despite a rather broadly “generalized” vertebrate morphology. Indeed, there are few morphological characters to distinguish subclades due to rampant homoplasy (Wake 1993).

  4. 4.

    See Gerson (2007) on the role of developments in research technology in the emergence of Evo-devo.

  5. 5.

    I was an undergraduate student in genetics at Berkeley (1973–1977). I took Wake’s evolution course in 1975 or 1976 and an independent study course with Wake on Gould’s Ontogeny and Phylogeny in 1977 to fulfill a requirement in biological diversity. Wake’s student, James Hanken, was my TA. Lewontin’s book was required reading, Alan Wilson (my biochemistry teacher) was making a splash with his innovative studies of rates of evolution, and Pere Alberch, my classmate in embryology, was becoming an innovator in thinking about evolution and development. I arrived at Chicago as a graduate student after Lewontin had left (I got his office on the 4th floor in the Zoology building), but the electrophoresis and phylogenetics revolutions were still fresh in Lynn Throckmorton’s teaching.

  6. 6.

    In biology, these were taxon-based disciplines (zoology, botany) with taxon-based specialties (mammalogy, malacology, protozoology, phytology, or pteridology); see Gerson (1998). One scientist’s problem is another scientist’s tool, so the distinction cannot be all that sharp.

  7. 7.

    “Periodization” is a way of describing how embryologists model developmental processes by dividing them into stages in order to express a narrative structure in terms of hypotheses of developmental fate susceptible to empirical testing (Griesemer 1996). Here, I apply similar reasoning in discussing conceptual development of the histories of biological specialties.

  8. 8.

    Shubin was a Miller post-doc at Berkeley and worked closely there with Wake. Shubin had been a graduate student at Harvard, where he worked closely with Pere Alberch, one of Wake’s students.

  9. 9.

    As benchmark, note that the TCIP/IP internet protocol and GenBank both launched in 1982.

  10. 10.

    Not that molecular evolution per se was uninteresting, but it is not especially germane to Wake’s story or to the role of evolutionary morphology in Evo-devo other than by adding yet another contrast between selection and alternative evolutionary mechanisms (drift).

  11. 11.

    It is important to emphasize that while I focus on David Wake, many colleagues, collaborators, post-docs, and students have been involved, including: Jessica Bolker (New Hampshire and Shoals Marine Laboratory), Allan Larson (Washington University), Neil Shubin (University of Chicago), Stephen Stearns (Yale), Gerhard Roth (Bremen), and Marvalee Wake (Emerita Professor of Integrative Biology, Berkeley), among others. Space does not permit a wider report on the spread of Wake’s “salamander platform” to other investigators or research organizations.

  12. 12.

    See also Bolker (2009) for a distinction between exemplars and surrogates.

  13. 13.

    Contingent distributions over all life on Earth would turn out to be fundamental if those patterns would appear again if “life’s tape” were rewound and replayed (see Gould 1989).

  14. 14.

    This distinction is similar to the one made by Gerson (2007) between part-whole and instance-kind relations. Gerson argues that there was a general shift in twentieth century biology from the former to the latter, and that this helps explain why certain specialties were excluded from the evolutionary synthesis, which emerged as an instance-kind sort of field, and why specialties that formed the Evo-devo juncture were all or mostly part-whole specialties. See also Winther (2006) on “compositional” biology.

  15. 15.

    Here I am using “problem” in yet a third way (cf. footnote 1). ‘Problem’ here refers to some environmental “challenge” “solved” by organisms. This is the sense of the term ‘problem’ that Lewontin (1978) and Gould and Lewontin (1979) found fault with in their critique of adaptationism. Organisms or species do not “solve” “problems” “posed” by “the environment,” according to their critique. It would take me too far afield to address this criticism by constructing a fully adequate set of terms to talk about “problems.” So, I commit their adaptationist fallacy on this occasion for the sake of convenience.

  16. 16.

    Wake’s publication list up to 2012 has been extremely useful as an aid to building my narrative (Wake n.d.). Given the immensity of Wake’s oeuvre, I can only sample a few representative works and must ignore his work on a variety of interrelated topics, such as global biodiversity.

  17. 17.

    This is not intended as a complete list of significant packages of phenomena developed in the Wake Lab, but only a description of some that were particularly relevant to Evo-devo work.

References

  • Alberch, P. 1980. Ontogenesis and morphological diversification. American Zoologist 20: 653–667.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alberch, P. 1981. Convergence and parallelism in foot morphology in the Neotropical salamander genus, Bolitoglossa. I. Function. Evolution 35: 84–100.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alberch, P. 1982. Developmental constraints in evolutionary processes. In Evolution and development, ed. J.T. Bonner, 213–332. Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alberch, P. 1989. The logic of monsters: evidence for internal constraint in development and evolution. Geobios 12: 21–57.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alberch, P., and J. Alberch. 1981. Heterochronic mechanisms of morphological diversification and evolutionary change in the Neotropical salamander Bolitoglossa occidentalis (Amphibia: Plethodontidae). Journal of Morphology 167: 249–264.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alberch, P., and M. Blanco. 1996. Evolutionary patterns in ontogenetic transformation: From laws to regularities. International Journal of Developmental Biology 40: 845–858.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alberch, P., and E.A. Gale. 1983. Size dependence during the development of the amphibian foot. Colchicine-induced digital loss and reduction. Journal of Embryology and Experimental Morphology 76: 177–197.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alberch, P., and E.A. Gale. 1985. A developmental analysis of an evolutionary trend: Digital reduction in amphibians. Evolution 39: 8–23.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alberch, P., S.J. Gould, G. Oster, and D. Wake. 1979. Size and shape in ontogeny and phylogeny. Paleobiology 5: 296–317.

    Google Scholar 

  • Allen, G. 1975. The introduction of Drosophila into the study of heredity and evolution, 1900–1910. Isis 66: 322–333.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ankeny, R. 2001. Model organisms as models: Understanding the ‘lingua franca’ of the human genome project. Philosophy of Science 68: S251–S261.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ankeny, R. 2007. Wormy logic: Model organisms as case-based reasoning. In Science without laws: Model systems, cases, exemplary narratives, ed. A.N.H. Creager, E. Lunbeck, and M. Norton Wise, 46–58. Chapel Hill: Duke University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ankeny, R. 2010. Historiographic considerations on model organisms: Or, how the mureaucracy may be limiting our understanding of contemporary genetics and genomics. History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences 32: 91–104.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ankeny, R., and S. Leonelli. 2011. What’s so special about model organisms? Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, Part A 42: 313–323.

    Google Scholar 

  • Autumn, K., M.J. Ryan, and D.B. Wake. 2002. Integrating historical and mechanistic biology enhances the study of adaptation. The Quarterly Review of Biology 77: 383–408.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bolker, J.A. 1995. Model systems in developmental biology. BioEssays 17: 451–455.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bolker, J.A. 2009. Exemplary and surrogate models: Two modes of representation in biology. Perspectives in Biology and Medicine 52: 485–499.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bonner, J.T. (ed.). 1982. Evolution and development. Report of the Dahlem workshop on evolution and development Berlin 1981, May 10–15. Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Burian, R. 1993. How the choice of experimental organism matters: Epistemological reflections on an aspect of biological practice. Journal of the History of Biology 26: 351–367.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carroll, S.B. 2005. Endless forms most beautiful: The new science of Evo-devo. New York: Norton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Churchill, F. 1997. Life before model systems: General zoology at August Weismann’s institute. American Zoologist 37: 260–268.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clarke, A., and J. Fujimura (eds.). 1992. The right tools for the job: At work in twentieth century life sciences. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clause, B. 1993. The Wistar rat as a right choice: Establishing mammalian standards and the ideal of a standardized mammal. Journal of the History of Biology 26: 329–350.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, E. 1982. Evolutionary change in genomic regulatory organization: Speculations on the origins of novel biological structure. In Evolution and development, ed. J.T. Bonner, 65–84. Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, E. 2001. Genomic regulatory systems. New York: Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dietrich, M. 1998. Paradox and persuasion: Negotiating the place of molecular evolution within evolutionary biology. Journal of the History of Biology 31: 85–111.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eldredge, N., and J. Cracraft. 1980. Phylogenetic patterns and the evolutionary process. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Evans, J. 2007. Start-ups in science: Entrepreneurs, diverse backing, and novelty outside business. In The sociology of entrepreneurship, Research in the sociology of organizations, vol. 25, ed. M. Ruef and M. Lounsbury, 261–305. Bradford: Emerald.

    Google Scholar 

  • Evans, D., A. Hagiu, and R. Schmalensee. 2006. Invisible engines: How software platforms drive innovation and transform industries. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Felsenstein, J. 2001. The troubled growth of statistical phylogenetics. Systematic Biology 50: 465–467.

    Google Scholar 

  • Felsenstein, J. 2004. Inferring phylogenies. Sunderland: Sinauer Associates.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fujimura, J. 1996. Crafting science: A sociohistory of the quest for the genetics of cancer. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gerhart, J., and M. Kirschner. 1997. Cells, embryos, and evolution: Toward a cellular and developmental understanding of phenotypic variation and evolutionary adaptability. Malden: Blackwell Science.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gerson, E.M. 1976. On “quality of life”. American Sociological Review 41: 793–806.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gerson, E.M. 1998. The American system of research: Evolutionary biology, 1890–1950. PhD dissertation, Department of Sociology, University of Chicago.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gerson, E.M. 2007. The juncture of evolutionary and developmental biology. In From embryology to Evo-devo: A history of developmental evolution, ed. M. Laubichler and J. Maienschein, 435–463. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ghiselin, M.T. 1980. The failure of morphology to assimilate Darwinism. In The evolutionary synthesis, ed. E. Mayr and W. Provine, 180–193. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ghiselin, M.T. 1997. Metaphysics and the origin of species. Albany: SUNY Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ghiselin, M.T. 2006. The failure of morphology to contribute to the modern synthesis. Theory in Biosciences 124: 309–316.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert, S. 2009. The adequacy of model systems for Evo-devo: Modeling the formation of organisms/modeling the formation of society. In Mapping the future of biology, eds. A. Barberousse, M. Morange, and T. Pradeu, 57–68, 155–169. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert, S.F., and J.A. Bolker. 2001. Homologies of process: Modular elements of embryonic construction. Journal of Experimental Zoology (Molecular and Developmental Evolution) 291: 1–12.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert, S.F., J.M. Opitz, and R.A. Raff. 1996. Resynthesizing evolutionary and developmental biology. Developmental Biology 173: 357–372.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gould, S.J. 1977. Ontogeny and phylogeny. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press/Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gould, S.J. 1989. Wonderful life, the Burgess Shale and the nature of history. New York: WW Norton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gould, S.J., and R.C. Lewontin. 1979. The spandrels of San Marco and the Panglossian paradigm: A critique of the adaptationist programme. Proceedings of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences 205: 581–598.

    Google Scholar 

  • Griesemer, J.R. 1996. Periodization and models in historical biology. In Memoirs of the California Academy of Sciences, New perspectives on the history of life, vol. 20, ed. M.T. Ghiselin and G. Pinna, 19–30. San Francisco: California Academy of Sciences.

    Google Scholar 

  • Griesemer, J.R. 2013. Integration of approaches in David Wake’s model-taxon research platform for evolutionary morphology. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 44: 525–536.

    Google Scholar 

  • Griesemer, J.R., and M.J. Wade. 1988. Laboratory models, causal explanation and group selection. Biology & Philosophy 3: 67–96.

    Google Scholar 

  • Griesemer, J.R., and G. Yamashita. 2005. Zeitmanagement bei modellsystemen. Drei beispiele aus der evolutionsbiologie. In Lebendige Zeit, ed. H. Schmidgen, 213–241. Berlin: Kulturverlag Kadmos.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haber, M. 2005. The centrality of phylogenetic thinking. PhD dissertation, Department of Philosophy, University of California, Davis.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hall, B.K. 2000. Evo-devo or devo-evo—does it matter? Evolution & Development 2: 177–178.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hanken, J. 1982. Appendicular skeletal morphology in minute salamanders, genus Thorius (Amphibia: Plethodontidae): Growth regulation, adult size determination, and natural variation. Journal of Morphology 174: 57–77.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hanken, J. 1983. Miniaturization and its effects on cranial morphology in plethodontid salamanders, genus Thorius (Amphibia: Plethodontidae). II. The fate of the brain and sense organs and their role in skull morphogenesis and evolution. Journal of Morphology 177: 255–268.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hanken, J. 1993. Model systems versus outgroups: Alternative approaches to the study of head development and evolution. American Zoologist 33: 448–456.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hanken, J., and D. Wake. 1993. Miniaturization of body size: Organismal consequences and evolutionary significance. Annual Review of Ecology and Systematics 24: 501–519.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hanken, J., and D. Wake. 1998. Biology of tiny animals: Systematics of the minute salamanders (Thorius: Plethodontidae) from Veracruz and Puebla, México, with descriptions of five new species. Copeia 1998: 312–345.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hedges, S. 2003. The origin and evolution of model organisms. Nature Reviews Genetics 3: 838–849.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hennig, W. 1965. Phylogenetic systematics. Annual Review of Entomology 10: 97–116.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hennig, W. 1966. Phylogenetic systematics. Trans. D. Davis and R. Zangerl. Urbana: University of Illinois Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hull, D. 1988. Science as a process. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jaekel, M., and D.B. Wake. 2007. Developmental processes underlying the evolution of a derived foot morphology in salamanders. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America 104: 20437–20442.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kay, L. 1993. The molecular vision of life: Caltech, the Rockefeller Foundation, and the rise of the new biology. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kellogg, E., and H. Shaffer. 1993. Model organisms in evolutionary studies. Systematic Biology 42: 409–414.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kohler, R.E. 1994. Lords of the fly: Drosophila genetics and the experimental life. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, T. 1970. The structure of scientific revolutions. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Larson, A., D. Wake, L. Maxson, and R. Highton. 1981. A molecular phylogenetic perspective on the origins of morphological novelties in the salamanders of the tribe Plethodontini (Amphibia, Plethodontidae). Evolution 35: 405–422.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laudan, L. 1977. Progress and its problems. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leonelli, S. 2007. Weed for thought: Using Arabidopsis thaliana to understand plant biology. PhD dissertation, Vrije Universiteit, Amsterdam.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewontin, R. 1974. The genetic basis of evolutionary change. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewontin, R. 1978. Adaptation. Scientific American 239: 213–230.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lombard, R.E., and D.B. Wake. 1976. Tongue evolution in the lungless salamanders, family Plethodontidae. I. Introduction, theory and a general model of dynamics. Journal of Morphology 148: 265–286.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lombard, R.E., and D.B. Wake. 1977. Tongue evolution in the lungless salamanders, family Plethodontidae. II. Function and evolutionary diversity. Journal of Morphology 153: 39–80.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lombard, R.E., and D.B. Wake. 1986. Tongue evolution in the lungless salamanders, family Plethodontidae. IV. Phylogeny of plethodontid salamanders and the evolution of feeding dynamics. Systematic Zoology 35: 532–551.

    Google Scholar 

  • Love, A.C. 2003. Evolutionary morphology, innovation, and the synthesis of evolutionary and developmental biology. Biology & Philosophy 18: 309–345.

    Google Scholar 

  • Love, A.C. 2006. Evolutionary morphology and evo–devo: Hierarchy and novelty. Theory in Biosciences 124: 317–333.

    Google Scholar 

  • Love, A.C. 2008. From philosophy to science (to natural philosophy): Evolutionary developmental perspectives. The Quarterly Review of Biology 83: 65–76.

    Google Scholar 

  • Love, A., and R. Raff. 2003. Knowing your ancestors: Themes in the history of Evo-devo. Evolution & Development 5: 327–330.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maderson, P.F.A., P. Alberch, B.C. Goodwin, S.J. Gould, A. Hoffman, J.D. Murray, D.M. Raup, A. de Ricqlès, A. Seilacher, G.P. Wagner, and D.B. Wake. 1982. The role of development in macroevolutionary change: Group report. In Evolution and development, ed. J.T. Bonner, 279–312. Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maxson, L., and D. Wake. 1981. Albumin evolution and its phylogenetic implications in the plethodontid salamander genera Pseudoeurycea and Chiropterotriton. Herpetologica 37: 109–117.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maxson, L., R. Highton, and D. Wake. 1979. Albumin evolution and its phylogenetic implications in the plethodontid salamander genera Plethodon and Ensatina. Copeia 1979: 502–508.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maynard Smith, J., R.M. Burian, S.A. Kauffman, P. Alberch, J. Campbell, B.C. Goodwin, R. Lande, D.M. Raup, and L. Wolpert. 1985. Developmental constraints and evolution. The Quarterly Review of Biology 60: 265–287.

    Google Scholar 

  • Metscher, B., and P. Ahlberg. 1999. Zebrafish in context: Uses of a laboratory model in comparative studies. Developmental Biology 210: 1–14.

    Google Scholar 

  • National Institutes of Health (n.d.). Model Organisms for Biomedical Research. Available online. http://www.nih.gov/science/models/. Accessed 6 March 2012.

  • Olsson, L., U. Hoßfeld, and O. Breidbach. 2006. From evolutionary morphology to the modern synthesis and “Evo-devo”: Historical and contemporary perspectives. Theory in Biosciences 124: 259–263.

    Google Scholar 

  • Parra-Olea, G., M. García-París, and D.B. Wake. 2004. Molecular diversification of salamanders of the tropical American genus Bolitoglossa (Caudata: Plethodontidae) and its evolutionary and biogeographical implications. Biological Journal of the Linnean Society 81: 325–346.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pigliucci, M., and G. Müller (eds.). 2010. Evolution: The extended synthesis. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rader, K. 2004. Making mice: Standardizing animals for American Biomedical Research, 1900–1955. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raff, R., and A. Love. 2004. Kowalevsky, comparative evolutionary embryology, and the intellectual lineage of Evo-devo. Journal of Experimental Zoology (Molecular and Developmental Evolution) 302B: 19–34.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roth, G., and D. Wake. 1983. Motor innervation of the projectile tongue of plethodontid salamanders. American Zoologist 23: 926.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roth, G., and D.B. Wake. 1985. Trends in the functional morphology and sensorimotor control of feeding behaviour in salamanders: An example of the role of internal dynamics in evolution. Acta Biotheoretica 34: 175–192.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roth, G., and D. Wake. 1989. Conservatism and innovation in the evolution of feeding in vertebrates. In Complex organismal functions: Integration and evolution in vertebrates, ed. D.B. Wake and G. Roth, 7–21. Chichester: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roth, G., D. Wake, M. Wake, and G. Rettig. 1984. Distribution of accessory and hypoglossal nerves in the hindbrain and spinal cord of lungless salamanders, family Plethodontidae. Neuroscience Letters 44: 53–57.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roth, G., J. Blanke, and D. Wake. 1994. Cell size predicts morphological complexity in the brains of frogs and salamanders. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America 91: 4796–4800.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sanderson, M., and L. Hufford. 1996. Homoplasy and the evolutionary process: An afterword. In Homoplasy, the recurrence of similarity in evolution, ed. M.J. Sanderson and L. Hufford, 327–330. San Diego: Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sessions, S., and A. Larson. 1987. Developmental correlates of genome size in plethodontid salamanders and their implications for genome evolution. Evolution 41: 1239–1251.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shubin, N., and D. Wake. 1996. Phylogeny, variation, and morphological integration. American Zoologist 36: 51–60.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sober, E. 1988. Reconstructing the past: Parsimony, evolution, and inference. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sunderland, M.E. 2012. Collections-based research at Berkeley’s Museum of Vertebrate Zoology. Historical Studies in the Natural Sciences 42: 83–113.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sunderland, M.E. 2013. Teaching natural history at the Museum of Vertebrate Zoology. The British Journal for the History of Science 46: 97–121.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sunderland, M.E. (in preparation). Making a model taxon: The development of Ensatina eschscholtzii as a model for studying evolution.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wake, D.B. 1966. Comparative osteology and evolution of the lungless salamanders, family Plethodontidae. Memoirs of the California Academy of Sciences 4: 1–111.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wake, D.B. 1978. Shape, form, development, ecology, genetics, and evolution. Review of Ontogeny and Phylogeny, by S.J. Gould. Paleobiology 4: 96–99

    Google Scholar 

  • Wake, D.B. 1982. Functional and evolutionary morphology. Perspectives in Biology and Medicine 25: 603–620.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wake, D.B. 1991. Homoplasy: The result of natural selection, or evidence of design limitations? American Naturalist 138: 543–567.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wake, D.B. 1993. Phylogenetic and taxonomic issues relating to salamanders of the family Plethodontidae. Herpetologica 49: 229–237.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wake, D.B. 1996. Introduction. In Homoplasy, the recurrence of similarity in evolution, ed. M.J. Sanderson and L. Hufford, xvii–xxv. San Diego: Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wake, D.B. 1998. Pere Alberch (1954–1998): Synthesizer of development and evolution. Nature 393: 632.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wake, D.B. 2002. On the scientific legacy of Stephen Jay Gould. Evolution 56: 2346.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wake, D.B. 2003. Homology and homoplasy. In Keywords and concepts in evolutionary developmental biology, ed. B.K. Hall and W.M. Olson, 191–201. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wake, D.B. 2009. What salamanders have taught us about evolution. Annual Review of Ecology, Evolution & Systematics 40: 333–352.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wake, D.B. n.d. Publications of David B. Wake http://ib.berkeley.edu/labs/wake/Papers.html. Accessed 3 July 2012.

  • Wake, D.B., and A. Larson. 1987. A multidimensional analysis of an evolving lineage. Science 238: 42–48.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wake, D.B., and E. Lombard. 1971. Functional aspects of tongue projection mechanisms in plethodontid salamanders. Herpetological Review 3: 108.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wake, D.B., and J.F. Lynch. 1976. The distribution, ecology, and evolutionary history of plethodontid salamanders in tropical America. Los Angeles County Museum of Natural History Science Bulletin 25: 1–65.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wake, D.B., L. Maxson, and G. Wurst. 1978. Genetic differentiation, albumin evolution, and their biogeographic implications in plethodontid salamanders of California and southern Europe. Evolution 32: 529–539.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wake, D.B., P. Mabee, J. Hanken, and G. Wagner. 1991. Development and evolution—the emergence of a new field. In The unity of evolutionary biology: Proceedings of the fourth international congress of systematic and evolutionary biology, vol. 1, ed. E.C. Dudley, 582–588. Portland: Dioscorides Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wake, D.B., M. Wake, and C. Specht. 2011. Homoplasy: From detecting pattern to determining process and mechanism of evolution. Science 331: 1032–1035.

    Google Scholar 

  • Waters, C.K. 1998. Causal regularities in the biological world of contingent distributions. Biology & Philosophy 13: 5–26.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wiley, E.D., D. Siegel-Causey, and V. Funk Brooks. 1991. The complete cladist: A primer of phylogenetic procedures. Lawrence: The University of Kansas Museum of Natural History.

    Google Scholar 

  • Winther, R.G. 2006. Parts and theories in compositional biology. Biology & Philosophy 21: 471–499.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wray, G. 1996. Review of Homoplasy: The recurrence of similarity in evolution. eds. M. Sanderson, and L. Hufford. The Quarterly Review of Biology 73: 210–211.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I thank Alan Love for organizing the workshop, incredible patience and care in reading the manuscript, and many suggestions that greatly improved the paper and its argument. Thanks also to the other workshop participants, especially David Wake and James Hanken, for helpful discussion. I thank Elihu Gerson for comments on the manuscript, discussion and support. Thanks to the California Academy of Sciences History and Philosophy of Biology Discussion Group for providing a willing audience and the UC Davis Herbert A. Young Society Dean’s Fellowship (2011–2014) and NSF grant SES-0823401 for support.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to James R. Griesemer .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2015 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Griesemer, J.R. (2015). What Salamander Biologists Have Taught Us About Evo-devo. In: Love, A. (eds) Conceptual Change in Biology. Boston Studies in the Philosophy and History of Science, vol 307. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-9412-1_13

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics