Skip to main content

Orbital Symmetry, Idealization, and the Kairetic Account of Scientific Explanation

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Philosophy of Chemistry

Part of the book series: Boston Studies in the Philosophy and History of Science ((BSPS,volume 306))

  • 2298 Accesses

Abstract

Michael Strevens’ kairetic account of scientific explanation is an important recent addition to the philosophy of scientific explanation. Amongst other things, he offers a relatively positive account of idealized explanation. Given that idealization is an important part of the practice of chemistry, his account should be of interest to the philosophers of chemistry. This contribution explores the relationship between explanation and idealizations in quantum chemistry. In spite of the virtues of Strevens’ causal account of scientific explanation, it nonetheless fails to adequately capture the nature and function of explanatory idealization in chemistry. Most importantly, Strevens’ account cannot address the idealization of causal difference-makers. While Strevens has good reasons to reject idealizations such as these, some of the most important developments in the modelling of reaction mechanisms in the last 50 years demonstrate that idealized models may well distort the causal story but nevertheless provide veridical explanations. I sketch the idea that orbital symmetry models of organic reactions explain by detaching difference-making from causal influence. The result is that symmetry is a non-causal difference-maker.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 99.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    I focus on Strevens’ ideas concerning explanation in deterministic systems.

  2. 2.

    For example, in order to explain why all normal ravens are naturally black, it is not enough to posit a mechanism described by a causal model that cites the relevant biochemical laws, and physiological and environmental conditions. To causally entail, and thus to explain the blackness of ravens, one must also cite the basing generalization “All normal ravens have P”, where P stands for the appropriate physiological properties (ibid, pp. 228–229). Basing generalizations can be physically contingent, physically necessary or perhaps metaphysically necessary, but one thing to note is that they need not be causal generalizations. Hence non-causal factors can play a role in the explanation, a theme I will reprise below. A basing pattern of phenomena corresponding to a basing generalization play an explanatory function in a manner like initial conditions in event explanation. A major difference between basing patterns and initial conditions is that since the former concern regularity explanation, they include not just actual but also counterfactual states of affairs (p. 235). For basing generalizations to play an explanatory function requires that they are subject to counterfactual constraints, the details of which I omit here (but see Strevens 2008 Sect. 7.3).

  3. 3.

    See Fisher (2006).

  4. 4.

    According to Strevens, individuating models that explain in the ontological sense must be carried out by attending to not only the setup but also to the “follow-through” – a deduction of the explanatory target from the setup, which “represents the way in which [the difference-makers] make a difference” (ibid, p. 319). By taking the follow-through into account one can individuate canonical and idealized models because the former “contains more objectively explanatory information than the idealized model” (ibid, p. 320).

  5. 5.

    In other words, it does not mean that the value for the parameter makes no difference; it is just that whatever value it does take it will not make a difference to the occurrence of the explanatory target, or that the value must fall within a certain range (ibid, p. 320).

  6. 6.

    This would require a defense of the ontological autonomy of chemistry. For an example of such a defense, see Lombardi and Lambarca (2005).

  7. 7.

    Outside the context of an explanatory framework, Strevens argues that black box explanations do not causally entail their targets and are incohesive (multiply-realizable – realised by diverse causal mechanisms) (ibid, p. 153).

  8. 8.

    For example, a thermally allowed cycloaddition is the 4 + 2 cycloaddition of ethene and butadiene, i.e. the Diels-Alder reaction. The corresponding selection rule is: m + n = 4q + 2, where m and n are numbers of pi-electrons, q is an integer 0, 1, 2… (Hoffmann and Woodward 1968, p. 827).

  9. 9.

    An influential interpretation of Curie’s principle is provided by Chalmers (1970). See also Earman (2004).

References

  • Brading K, Castellani E (2007) Symmetries and invariance in classical physics. In: Butterfield J, Earman J (eds) Handbook of the philosophy of physics. North-Holland, pp 1331–1367

    Google Scholar 

  • Brading K, Castellani E (2013) Symmetry and symmetry breaking. In: Zalta EN (ed) The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy, Spring 2013 edn. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2013/entries/symmetry-breaking/

  • Brush SG (1999) Dynamics of theory change in chemistry: part 2. Benzene and molecular orbitals, 1945–1980. Stud Hist Philos Sci 30(2):263–302

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers A (1970) Curie’s principle. Br J Philos Sci 21(2):133–148

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dewar MJS (1989) A critique of frontier orbital theory. J Mol Struct (Theochem) 200:301–323

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Doering W von E, Roth WR (1962) The overlap of two allyl radicals or a four-centered transition state in the cope rearrangement. Tetrahedron 18:67–74

    Article  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Earman J (2004) Laws, symmetry, and symmetry breaking: invariance, conservation principles, and objectivity. PSA 2002 Presidential Address, Philos Sci 71:1227–1241

    Google Scholar 

  • Fisher G (2006) The autonomy of models and explanation: anomalous molecular rearrangements in early twentieth-century physical organic chemistry. Stud Hist Philos Sci A 37:562–584

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gavroglu K, Simoes A (2012) Neither physics nor chemistry: a history of quantum chemistry. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Hoffmann R, Woodward RB (1968) The conservation of orbital symmetry. Acc Chem Res 1:17–22

    Article  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Houk KN, Gonzalez J, Li Y (1995) Pericyclic reaction transition states: passions and punctilios, 1935–1995. Acc Chem Res 28:81–91

    Article  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Ismael J (1997) Curie’s principle. Synthese 110:167–190

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lombardi O, Labarca M (2005) The ontological autonomy of the chemical world. Found Chem 7:125–148

    Article  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Scerri E (2001) The recently claimed observation of atomic orbitals and some related philosophical issues. Philos Sci 68(3), Supplement: Proceedings of the 2000 Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association. Part 1: Contributed Papers, pp S76–S88

    Google Scholar 

  • Strevens M (2008) Depth: an account of scientific explanation. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Weisberg M (2004) Qualitative theory and chemical explanation. Philos Sci 71:1071–1081

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Grant Fisher .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2015 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Fisher, G. (2015). Orbital Symmetry, Idealization, and the Kairetic Account of Scientific Explanation. In: Scerri, E., McIntyre, L. (eds) Philosophy of Chemistry. Boston Studies in the Philosophy and History of Science, vol 306. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-9364-3_13

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics