Skip to main content

Anti-perfectionist Childrearing

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
The Nature of Children's Well-Being

Part of the book series: Children’s Well-Being: Indicators and Research ((CHIR,volume 9))

Abstract

This paper defends a reasonably controversial view about how we should understand the morally appropriate relationship between parent and child, which I call parental anti-perfectionism. On this view, parents act illegitimately if they enroll their child into religious practices that are controversial in society. The paper clarifies and sketches an argument for parental anti-perfectionism, and defends it against the charges that the ideal is too vague, provides for only an insipid upbringing, or that it requires parents to neglect their children.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    For a discussion of dignity and self-respect that suggests this view, see Dworkin (2011: pp. 202–209).

  2. 2.

    The distinction between the three different kinds of permissibility draws on Parfit (2011: pp. 150–151).

  3. 3.

    Brighouse and Swift (2009) set out a conception of familial relationship goods, which might be thought to rescue the compatibility of perfectionism and parents sharing their values with their child. However, it is not obvious that the value of parents and children having common goals is wholly independent of the intrinsic value of the goals that they pursue together.

  4. 4.

    Many liberal educational theorists endorse what I call the popular view. Perhaps the most prominent statement of it is Feinberg (1992).

  5. 5.

    For the observation that this view permits parents to encourage their child to adopt goals that diminish her well-being, see Fowler (2010). Perhaps it is consistent with the popular view for the state to prohibit parents acting with an inappropriate attitude towards their child. For example, suppose I am a devout Christian but regard my child as not entitled to an upbringing that introduces her to Christianity, because children are morally inferior to adults and, therefore, their well-being matters less. In that case, the state might legitimately claim that I have the wrong attitude towards my children that is revealed by the fact that I refuse to offer my child the opportunity to pursue what I take to be the right way to live. That attitude might be wrongful and, perhaps, an appropriate basis for creating a criminal wrong, even if refusing my child an introduction to Christianity does, in fact, improve her life (because, suppose, Christian lifestyles diminish people’s well-being). For discussion of the right to an attitude, as applied to human rights, see Dworkin (2011: pp. 335–339).

  6. 6.

    Here I summarize and clarify the argument of Clayton (2006, Chap. 4).

  7. 7.

    One objection to my focus on enrolment is that it rests on the controversial view that the permissibility of acts is not independent of the aims that motivate the agent. For a critique of that view, see Scanlon (2008). I lack the space to deal with this objection here. However, I simply note that, like its political counterpart, anti-perfectionist parenting is primarily an account of the reasons that ought to motivate individuals. The precise relationship between parental motivation and the permissibility of their actions, I leave to discuss on another occasion.

  8. 8.

    I am conscious that the position I expound here differs in many important respects from the way in which Rawls deploys the capacity for a conception of the good. For an examination of those differences and an argument for departing from Rawls, see Clayton (2006: pp. 24–27).

  9. 9.

    See, for example, McLaughlin (1984); worries of this kind are also expressed by Callan (2002).

  10. 10.

    Consider, for example, 1 Corinthians 13: 11, ‘When I was a child, I spoke like a child, I thought like a child, and reasoned like a child; when I became a man, I gave up childish ways’.

  11. 11.

    This is a familiar strategy within liberal thought. For an analogous argument for prohibiting trade on Sundays, see Mill ([1859] 2008: Ch. IV, par. 20).

  12. 12.

    For their instructive written comments, I thank Alex Bagattini, Sarah Hannan, Colin Macleod, Tom Parr, and Andrew Williams. I am also grateful for valuable discussions with Paul Bou-Habib, Chiara Cordelli, Tim Fowler, Hugh Lazenby, R. J. Leland, Adam Swift, Debra Satz, Victor Tadros, and audiences in Oxford and Stanford.

References

  • Brighouse, H., & Swift, A. (2009). Legitimate parental partiality. Philosophy and Public Affairs, 37, 43–80.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Callan, E. (2002). Autonomy, child-rearing, and good lives. In D. Archard & C. Macleod (Eds.), The morality and political status of children (pp. 118–141). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Cameron, C. (2012). Clayton on comprehensive enrolment. Journal of Political Philosophy, 20, 341–352.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clayton, M. (2006). Justice and legitimacy in upbringing. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Clayton, M. (2009). Reply to Morgan. Studies in Philosophy and Education, 28, 91–100.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clayton, M. (2012). The case against the comprehensive enrolment of children. Journal of Political Philosophy, 20, 353–364.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, R. (2011). Justice for hedgehogs. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feinberg, J. (1992). The child’s right to an open future. In Feinberg (Ed.), Freedom and fulfillment: Philosophical essays. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fowler, T. (2010). The problems of liberal neutrality in upbringing. Res Publica, 16, 367–381.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hannan, S. (2011). Balancing parental authority and children’s autonomy rights: A role-based solution. Oxford: Oxford University D. Phil.

    Google Scholar 

  • Locke, J. ([1690] 1988). In P. Laslett (Ed.), Two treatises of government. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Macleod, C. (2010). Primary goods, capabilities, and children. In H. Brighouse & I. Robeyns (Eds.), Measuring justice: Primary goods and capabilities (pp. 174–192). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • McLaughlin, T. H. (1984). Parental rights and the religious upbringing of children. Journal of Philosophy of Education, 18, 75–82.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mill, J.S. ([1859] 2008). In J. Gray (Ed.), On liberty and other essays. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morgan, J. (2009). Critical review of justice and legitimacy in upbringing. Studies in Philosophy and Education, 28, 79–89.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Parfit, D. (2011). On what matters. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. (2006). Political liberalism, paperback edition. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raz, J. (1989). Facing up: A reply. Southern California Law Review, 62, 1153–1236.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rousseau, J.-J. ([1762] 1978). In R. Masters (Ed.), On the social contract. New York: St. Martin’s Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scanlon, T. M. (2008). Moral dimensions: Permissibility, meaning, blame. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Matthew Clayton .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2015 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Clayton, M. (2015). Anti-perfectionist Childrearing. In: Bagattini, A., Macleod, C. (eds) The Nature of Children's Well-Being. Children’s Well-Being: Indicators and Research, vol 9. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-9252-3_8

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics