Skip to main content

Responsibility and Visions in the New and Emerging Technologies

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Responsibility in Nanotechnology Development

Part of the book series: The International Library of Ethics, Law and Technology ((ELTE,volume 13))

Abstract

One peculiarity of the technologies referred to as ‘new and emerging’, such as synthetic biology, the nanotechnologies, and the converging technologies, is their visionary character. Although applications exist now and there is much applied research, much of the current ethical and political debate is focused on possible technological developments, i.e. on technological visions. Since this visionary character is frequently not acknowledged, the future of the different forms of technology is often taken for granted, which makes it appear that the ethical and political discussion has developed following a dynamic of its own, engaging in problematic speculation. What does it mean to analyse the normative implications of technological visions? After discussing the different meanings of responsibility and providing some examples taken from the current debate on human enhancement, the aim of this article is to disentangle the implications of thinking about responsibility in relation to technological visions.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    See Coenen et al. (2009).

  2. 2.

    Ethics in Public Policy Making: The Case of Human Enhancement (EPOCH) is a European Commission FP7 Science in Society funded project, grant number SIS-CT-2010-266660 (http://epochproject.com).

  3. 3.

    To the present day there is no commonly shared and general definition of nanotechnology beyond a general identification of the study and control of matter at the molecular and atomic scales (i.e. a definition which gives a precise range or which refers to fields of application). With very few exceptions, it is difficult to find any kind of matter that would not qualify as an object of such nanoscale research: every branch of experimental science and technology nowadays deals with material objects structured at the nanoscale. There are various efforts in different continents to find a definition, which are influenced by the topics regarded as the most important in the local context. In October 2011 Europe adopted the ‘Recommendation on the definition of a nanomaterial’: ‘According to this recommendation, ‘nanomaterial’ means: ‘A natural, incidental or manufactured material containing particles, in an unbound state or as an aggregate or as an agglomerate and where, for 50 % or more of the particles in the number size distribution, one or more external dimensions is in the size range 1–100 nm. In specific cases and where warranted by concerns for the environment, health, safety or competitiveness the number size distribution threshold of 50 % may be replaced by a threshold between 1 and 50 %. By derogation from the above, fullerenes, graphene flakes and single wall carbon nanotubes with one or more external dimensions below 1 nm should be considered as nanomaterials.’ This recommendation states that, by December 2014, the EC will review the definition ‘in the light of experience and of scientific and technological developments. The review should particularly focus on whether the number size distribution threshold of 50 % should be increased or decreased.’ The absence of a commonly accepted definition of nanotechnologies has precise epistemological implications, because it influences the setting and legitimisation of scientific research areas and therefore the scope of the research. The setting of goals clearly has ethical implications, because goals and aims are shaped by society and because goals are matters of research policy-in particular through priority-setting. The definition of ‘nanotechnology’ varies depending on research priorities of different countries: (unlike the US, Asian countries such as China, Japan and Korea tend to emphasise material sciences and electronics, while African and Latin American countries focus on environmental sciences and medicine). Furthermore, the lack of a commonly accepted definition is ethically relevant because it opens the ethical discourse indefinitely and, as we will see, many authors tend to associate with nanoethics different kinds of problems (cf. Ferrari 2010).

  4. 4.

    Since in the project of ‘converging technologies’ the level of atomic manipulation is taken as the ultimate one and as the basis for creating a new world, the ‘integration from the nanoscale’ of these technologies is seen as determining a ‘tremendous improvement in human abilities and societal outcomes’ (Roco and Bainbridge 2002).

  5. 5.

    These arguments are: nature, dignity, the good life, utility, equity, autonomy, and rights (Patenaude et al. 2011).

  6. 6.

    According to the Oxford English Dictionary, the first use of the word ‘responsibility’ is in issue 63 of the ‘Federalist’ (1787), a text attributed to Alexander Hamilton. For a web version see: http://foundingfathers.info/federalistpapers/fed63.htm, accessed October 2, 2012. As regards the history of the term ‘responsibility’, see Villey (1977) and Henriot (1977).

  7. 7.

    The theme of mutual commitment is also confirmed by the Greek verb spendo, which means ‘to pour out as a drink offering’, ‘to make a solemn libation’ to the gods, hence ‘to engage oneself by a ritual act’, but also ‘to enter into an agreement’ as the gods are called to guarantee an action too (for example the victory in war).

  8. 8.

    In this respect, it could be noted that the term responsibility may also have been derived from the Latin verb responsare, which means ‘to be able to go against the mainstream’. Consequently, responsibility is the capacity to face the difficulties that could raise in fulfilling the assumed commitment, going also against the mainstream.

  9. 9.

    It should be noted that the expressions ‘moral obligation’ and ‘moral reason’ are not synonymous because the former expresses a stronger normative force than the latter. For a critical analysis of the use of ‘have a good reason to’ within Savulescu’s approach, see Marin (2012, pp. 113–115).

References

  • Annas, G. 2002. Cell division. Center for Genetics and Society. http://www.geneticsandsociety.org/article.php?id=164. Accessed 21 Oct 2012.

  • Béland, J.P., J. Patenaude, G.A. Legault, P. Boissy, and M. Parent. 2011. The social and ethical acceptability of NBICs for purposes of human enhancement: Why does the debate remain mired in impasse? NanoEthics 5(3): 295–307.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Berloznik, R., and Casert, R. 2006. Technology assessment on converging technology – Literature study and vision assessment. Background document for the STOA workshop ‘converging technologies in the 21st century: Heaven, hell or down to earth?’, Brussels, 27 June 2006.

    Google Scholar 

  • Borup, M., N. Brown, K. Konrad, and H. van Lente. 2006. The sociology of expectations in science and technology. Technology Analysis and Strategic Management 18(3/4): 285–298.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Coenen, C. 2010. Deliberating visions: The case of human enhancement in the discourse on nanotechnology and convergence. In Governing future technologies. Nanotechnology and the rise of an assessment regime, ed. M. Kaiser et al., 73–88. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Coenen, C., T. Fleischer, and M. Rader. 2004. Of visions, dreams, and nightmares: The debate on converging technologies. Technikfolgenabschätzung – Theorie und Praxis 13(3): 118–125.

    Google Scholar 

  • Coenen, C., M. Smits, M. Schuijff, P. Klaassen, L. Hennen, M. Rader, and G. Wolbring. 2009. Human enhancement study (IP/A/STOA/FWC/2005_28/SC32 and 39). Brussels: European Parliament. http://www.europarl.europa.eu/RegData/etudes/etudes/join/2009/429976/IPOL-JOIN_ET(2009)429976_EN.pdf. Accessed 24 Jun 2014.

  • Dupuy, J.-P. 2007. Some pitfalls in the philosophical foundations of nanoethics. The Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 32(3): 237–261.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ebbesen, M., S. Andersen, and F. Besenbacher. 2006. Ethics in nanotechnology: Starting from scratch? Bulletin of Science Technology Society 26(6): 451–462.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Felt, U., et al. 2007. Taking European knowledge society seriously. Report of the expert group on science and governance to the science, economy and society directorate, Directorate-General for Research, European Commission. http://ec.europa.eu/research/science-society/document_library/pdf_06/european-knowledge-society_en.pdf. Accessed 21 Oct 2012.

  • Ferrari, Arianna. 2010. Developments in the debate on nanoethics: Traditional approaches and the need for new kinds of analysis. NanoEthics 4(1): 27–52.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ferrari, A., C. Coenen, and A. Grunwald. 2012. Visions and ethics in current discourse on human enhancement. NanoEthics 6(3): 215–229. doi:10.1007/s11569-012-0155-1.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fukuyama, F. 2004. Transhumanism. Foreign Policy 144: 42–44.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Garcia, D. 1989. Fundamentos de bioetica. Madrid: EUDEMA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Garreau, R. 2005. Radical evolution. The promises and perils of enhancing our minds, our bodies – And what it means to be human. Toronto: Doubleday.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gordijn, B. 2005. Nanoethics: From utopian dreams and apocalyptic nightmares towards a more balanced view. Science and Engineering Ethics 11(4): 521–533.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grunwald, A. 2008. Auf dem Weg in eine nanotechnologische Zukunft: Philosophisch-ethische Fragen. Freiburg: Karl Alber.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harris, J. 2007. Enhancing evolution. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Henriot, J. 1977. Note sur la date et le sens de l’apparition du mot responsabilité. Archives de Philosophie du Droit 22: 58–62.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jonas, H. 1979. Das Prinzip Verantwortung: Versuch einer Ethik für die technologische Zivilisation. Suhrkamp: Frankfurt am Main.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lehrer, J. 2009. Neuroscience: Small, furry…and smart. Nature 461(7266): 862–864.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • MacDonald, L., and G.J.S. Boyce. 2008. Nanotechnology: Considering the complex ethical, legal, and societal issues with the parameters of human performance. NanoEthics 2(3): 265–275.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marin, F. 2012. Il bene del paziente e le sue metamorfosi nell’etica biomedica. Milano: Bruno Mondadori.

    Google Scholar 

  • McKibben, B. 2003. Designer genes. Orion, April 30. http://www.orionsociety.org/pages/om/03-3om/McKibben.html. Accessed 21 Oct 2012.

  • Nordmann, A. 2004. Converging technologies – Shaping the future of European societies. Report of the HLEG Foresighting the New Technology Wave. http://www.ntnu.no/2020/final_report_en.pdf. Accessed 21 Oct 2012.

  • Nordmann, A. 2007. If and then: A critique of speculative nanoethics. NanoEthics 1: 31–46.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nordmann, A., and A. Rip. 2009. Mind the gap revisited. Nature Nanotechnology 4(5): 273–274.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Outram, S.M. 2011. Ethical considerations in the framing of the cognitive enhancement debate. Neuroethics 5(2): 173–184.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Patenaude, J., G.A. Legault, J.P. Béland, P. Boissy, and M. Parent. 2011. Moral arguments in the debate over nanotechnologies: Are we talking past each other? NanoEthics 5(3): 285–293.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Quednow, B. 2011. Ethics of neuroenhancement: A phantom debate. BioSocieties 5(1): 153–156.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Racine, E., and C. Forlini. 2010. Cognitive enhancement, lifestyle choice or misuse of prescription drugs? Ethics blind spots in current debates. Neuroethics 3(1): 1–4.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roco, M., and W.S. Bainbridge (eds.). 2002. Converging technologies for improving human performance: Nanotechnology, biotechnology, information technology and cognitive science. Arlington: National Science Foundation.

    Google Scholar 

  • Saage, R. 2006. Konvergenztechnologische Zukunftsvisionen und der klassische Utopiediskurs. In Nanotechnologien im Kontext, ed. A. Nordmann, J. Schummer, and A. Schwarz, 179–194. Berlin: Akademische Verlagsgesellschaft.

    Google Scholar 

  • Savulescu, J. 2006. Justice, fairness, and enhancement. Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences 1093: 321–338.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Savulescu, J. 2007. Genetic interventions and the ethics of enhancement of human beings. In The Oxford handbook of bioethics, ed. B. Steinbock, 516–535. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Savulescu, J. 2009. Genetic enhancement. In A companion to bioethics, ed. H. Kuhse and P. Singer, 216–234. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Savulescu, J., A. Sandberg, and G. Kahane. 2011. Well-being and enhancement. In Enhancing human capacities, ed. J. Savulescu, R. ter Meulen, and G. Kahane, 3–18. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Schmidt, K.F. 2006. Nanofrontiers: Visions for the future of nanotechnology. Washington, DC: Project on Emerging Nanotechnologies.

    Google Scholar 

  • Selgelid, M. 2007. An argument against arguments for enhancement. Studies in Ethics, Law, and Technology 1(1): 1–7. doi:10.2202/1941–6008.1008.

    Google Scholar 

  • Singh, I., and K.J. Kelleher. 2010. Neuroenhancement in young people: Proposal for research, policy, and clinical management. AJOB Neuroscience 1(1): 3–16.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Turoldo, F. 2009. Bioetica ed etica della responsabilità: dai fondamenti teorici alle applicazioni pratiche. Assisi: Cittadella Editore.

    Google Scholar 

  • Turoldo, F. 2010. Ethics of responsibility in a multicultural context. Perspectives in Biology and Medicine 53(2): 174–185.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Villey, M. 1977. Esquisse historique sur le mot responsible. Archives de Philosophie du Droit 22: 45–58.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Arianna Ferrari .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2014 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Ferrari, A., Marin, F. (2014). Responsibility and Visions in the New and Emerging Technologies. In: Arnaldi, S., Ferrari, A., Magaudda, P., Marin, F. (eds) Responsibility in Nanotechnology Development. The International Library of Ethics, Law and Technology, vol 13. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-9103-8_2

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics