Skip to main content

Part of the book series: International Library of Ethics, Law, and the New Medicine ((LIME,volume 62))

  • 437 Accesses

Abstract

Most discussions about someone terminating her own life tend to focus either on utilitarian considerations or rights. For the latter, a number of people argue over whether we have a right to die , which I take to mean an entitlement to choose to end one’s own life. I see at least two problems with the right to die approach. Unfortunately, many arguments and positions are based primarily on the intuitions of those engaged, and therefore often turn into intuition pump battles. Secondly, basing arguments on rights gets us mired in the same problems that any rights talk encounters including, but not limited to, whether they are positive or negative, whether they can be overridden, and what justifies such a right. In this chapter, I am going to argue for a position that makes worries about a right to die moot. If there is an obligation at certain times and in certain circumstances to die, then a right to die is irrelevant. Moreover, if an obligation to die is possible, then it necessarily follows that choosing to die is morally right on some occasions. Doing what is right generally cannot be proscribed by others so it does not matter if there is a right to die.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Islam, for instance, prohibits all euthanasia “because it deprives the person of the right to life and the possibility of action”. (Muwahidi 1989, 48).

  2. 2.

    A more standard way to approach death is to argue that it is permissible to die or that there is some sort of right to die. Lebacqz and Engelhardt , for example, argue that there is a prima facie right to die (Lebacqz and Englehardt 1986, 85).

  3. 3.

    I will later argue that allowing oneself to die is generally a form of suicide.

  4. 4.

    Of course, it is probable and plausible to believe that there are far more instances of shortened life being permissible than rising to the level of a moral obligation.

  5. 5.

    I might be asserting too strong a position for Davis, but it seems in keeping with her arguments.

  6. 6.

    If there is an afterlife, then the force of this and other arguments depending on a total cessation of existence will have to be rethought. After all, if the afterlife is likely to be much better, then it would be rational on at least egoistic grounds to pursue self-death.

  7. 7.

    Poverty is not merely about financial wherewithal. Some people are raised in a financially poor situation but have flourishing lives.

  8. 8.

    Hardwig could agree with Overall, and then state that his criteria already include a condition that the person will not have the flourishing life Overall describes.

  9. 9.

    This ambiguity is a mistake: To leave a central term of this importance too vague or ambiguous will make disagreements rife as people talk past each other instead of discussing the same issue.

  10. 10.

    Some will argue for the permissibility of the four taking resources from the fifth, possibly on the grounds of maximizing utility, but the quantitative versus qualitative issue is not fundamental to this discussion.

  11. 11.

    Even in cases in which there are insufficient resources, Overall has an optimistic outlook for society’s ability to overcome this difficulty.

  12. 12.

    It should be noted that if we are going to have discussions about redistribution, then there cannot be a privileging of developed countries over developing countries. The mere fact the former has great wealth and power does not mean that individuals lucky enough to be born in them deserve the resources they take for granted as a right. I take it this is a point that Battin makes in her argument for some people to no longer take resources if they have already had their fair share.

  13. 13.

    The approach I am taking here is similar to Peter Windt’s (1980) Wittgensteinian analysis.

  14. 14.

    These are not desires formed intentionally, but rather desires that commit the agent to carrying out the intention.

  15. 15.

    This is also relevant to suicides and other takings of life.

  16. 16.

    I am not going to argue that there is one definition of suicide.

  17. 17.

    Part of this argument appears in my review of Cholbi’s Suicide at Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews.

  18. 18.

    This lack of time objection can also be used against Chisholm and Sidgwick’s position. It is difficult to see that there is an intention formed in these cases.

  19. 19.

    Sometimes, there seems to be confusion about what palliative care is. If it is merely a treatment or management of various kinds of pain from various sources, then it is not a form of euthanasia. Palliative care, in this sense, will also apply to a number of non-terminal cases, and is generally preferred by the Practical Principle if everything that is intrinsically valuable is respected as such and it is likely to result in the best outcome. However, if palliative care means an alternative to prolonging life, and that seems to be what it is in many proponents’ arguments (Pereira 2011; Omipidam 2013), then it is a form of passive euthanasia even if its primary intentions are directed toward managing pain and making the person feel positive about herself (Steffen and Cooley 2014). The main difference between it and active euthanasia is the difference between passive and active euthanasia.

  20. 20.

    A question arises as to what “true” suicides from acts of commission actually intend. My suspicion is that they intend the cessation of pain and suffering or some other end rather than their deaths. If this is true, then it becomes even clearer that these cases are morally identical and therefore should be labeled as suicides.

  21. 21.

    Gavin Fairbairn argues that refusal of treatment is a case of suicide, whereas jumping on a grenade is not (Fairbairn 1995, 114–7). What makes the two morally different is that in the latter, the agent really has no choice in the method of saving his friends; therefore, he was compelled in a significant way. Of course, the problem with Fairbairn’s ‘only one method’ argument is that the grenade jumper had the option of preserving his own life, even though that would have resulted in his friends’ deaths. Therefore, the grenade jumper committed suicide because there was a different, legitimate option open to him at the time.

  22. 22.

    Some writers argue that there is a moral distinction between the two. J.P. Bishop, for instance, claims that since voluntary active euthanasia’s purpose is to die, then there is no meaningfulness in the dying process as there is in passive euthanasia (Bishop 2006, 223).

  23. 23.

    I think that this difference is what motivates some to use the Doctrine of Double Effect to distinguish cases of permissible and impermissible actions when they are really considering better or worse situations and people.

  24. 24.

    The mere fact that a person is mentally ill in regard to an unrelated condition or at risk of suicide does not automatically render the person incompetent when it comes to making decisions about medical treatment or suicide. Moreover, it does not automatically permit outside agents, such as physicians or the state, to interfere in legitimate decision making (Callaghan et al. 2013, 384).

  25. 25.

    Neill Allen argues that “suicidal citizens have the right to require public authorities to take reasonable precautions to avoid their death if they ought to know of a real and immediate risk to life.” (Allen 2013, 356). Apparently being suicidal is sufficient to eliminate autonomy, but not the positive rights associated with remaining alive the individual is uninterested in having fulfilled.

  26. 26.

    Jeanette Hewitt notes that the rationality of suicide seems to be linked to whether it is performed to alleviate extreme physical or mental suffering. Suicide to stop extreme physical disorders are more likely to be justified than are those from mental suffering, in which it is automatically assumed that psychological conditions render the person incompetent. As a result, intervention is more often thought to be obligatory in the latter when not justified in the former (Hewitt 2013).

  27. 27.

    Brandt’s approach has the same problem as Prado’s: “The basic question a person must answer, in order to determine which world-course is best or rational for him to choose, is which he would choose under conditions of optimal use of information, when all of his desires are taken into account.” (Brandt 1975, 69).

    Although an ideal way to make a decision, Brandt’s standard is far too high for humanity. It is asking us to act as we would as perfectly rational people in a perfect society, but we are clearly not perfectly rational creatures with perfect access to all relevant information, yet we are still moral agents.

  28. 28.

    I think this example might be too simplistic. In order to have the different mental states, other states would have to be altered between the worlds so that the former mental states can exist.

  29. 29.

    I have argued in “Crimina Carnis and Morally Obligatory Suicide” that those who would engage in murder, terrorism, rape, pedophilia, genocide, and other morally horrific actions can lose their moral lives.

References

  • Ackerman, F. 2008. Bioethicists push for your death. The Providence Journal. http://www.projo.com/opinion/contributors/content/CT_ackerman30_09-30-08_KTBN7NQ_v10.1a566ce.html. Accessed 24 Aug 2014.

  • Allen, N. 2013. The right to life in a suicidal state. International Journal of Law and Psychiatry 36: 350–357.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alvarez, A. 1998. The history of suicide. In Last rights: Assisted suicide and euthanasia debated, ed. M.M. Uhlmann, 57–74. Grand Rapids: William B. Eerdmans Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baier, A.C. 1970. Act and intent. Journal of Philosophy 67: 648–658.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Battin, M.P. 1996. The death debate: ethical issues in suicide. Upper Saddle River: Prentice Hall Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Battin, M.P. 2000. Global life expectancies and the duty to die. In Is there a duty to die?, ed. J.M. Humber, and R.F. Almeder, 1–22. Totowa: Humana Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Beauchamp, T.L. 1986. What is suicide? In Ethical issues in death and dying, ed. R.W. Weir, 323–329. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bennett, M. 2000. Do we have a duty to die? In Is there a duty to die?, ed. J.M. Humber, and R.F. Almeder, 41–60. Totowa: Humana Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Bishop, J.O. 2006. Euthanasia, efficiency, and the historical distinction between killing a patient and allowing a person to die. Journal of Medical Ethics 32: 220–224.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bogen, J. 1998. Suicide and Virtue in Virtuous Persons, Vicious Deeds, ed. A.E. Hooke, 645–50. Mountain View: Mayfield Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boyle, J.M., Jr. and T.D. Sullivan, 1977. The diffusiveness of intention principle: A counter example, Philosophical Studies: 357–60.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brandt, R. 1975. The morality and rationality of suicide. In A handbook for the study of suicide, ed. S. Perlin, 61–76. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brandt, R. 1992. Morality, utilitarianism and rights. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brock, D. 1998. Life and death: Philosophical essays in biomedical ethics, 144–183. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Callaghan, S., et al. 2013. Risk of suicide is insufficient warrant for coercive treatment for mental illness. International Journal of Law and Psychiatry 36: 374–385.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Callahan, D. 1975. Vital distinctions, mortal questions. In Arguing euthanasia, ed. J.D. Moreno, 173–195. New York: Simon & Schuster.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chisholm, R. 1990. The structure of intention. Journal of Philosophy 67: 633–647.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cholbi, M. 2011. Suicide: The philosophical dimensions. Ontario: Broadview Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chow, P.I., and B.W. Roberts. 2014. Examining the relationship between changes in personality and changes in depression. International Journal of Psychiatry 51: 38–46.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davis, L.H. 1979. Theory of action. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davis, D. 1998. Why suicide is like contraception. In Physician assisted suicide, ed. M.P. Battin, R. Rhodes, and A. Silver, 113–122. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davis, D. 1999. Rational suicide and predictive genetic testing. The Journal of Clinical Ethics, Winter: 316–323.

    Google Scholar 

  • Donagan, A. 1987. Choice: The essential element of human action. New York: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Durkheim, E. 1951 Suicide: A study of sociology. Ed. George Simpson, trans. J.A Spaulding and G. Simpson, Glencoe: Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fairbairn, J.G. 1995. Contemplating suicide: The language and ethics of self harm. New Fetter Lane: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hardwig, J. 1997. Is there a duty to die? Hastings Center Report 21, no. 2: 32–42.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hewitt, J. 2013. Why are people with mental illness excluded from the rational suicide debate? International Journal of Law and Psychiatry 36: 358–365.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Holland, R.F. 1969. Suicide in Talk of God. Royal Institute of Philosophy Lectures, Vol. 2, 1967–8, ed. G.N.A. Vessey, 72–85. London: Macmillian.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hume, D. 1740. Treatise of Human Nature. London.

    Google Scholar 

  • Humphry, D. 1998. The case for rational suicide. In Last rights: Assisted suicide and euthanasia debated, ed. M.M. Uhlmann, 307–316. Grand Rapids: William B. Eerdmans Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. 1964. Groundwork of the Metaphysic of Morals. Trans. H. J. Paton. New York: Harper & Row Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. 1996. The Metaphysics of Morals. Trans. Mary Gregory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kissell, J.L. 2000. Grandma, the GNP, and the Duty to Die? In Is there a duty to die?, ed. J.M. Humber, and R.F. Almeder, 191–204. Totowa: Humana Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Lebacqz, K., and H.T. Englehardt Jr. 1986. Suicide and covenant. In Ethical issues in death and dying, ed. R.W. Weir, 345–353. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Libet, B., et al. 1983. Time of conscious intention to act in relation to onset of cerebral activity readiness-potential: The unconscious initiation of a freely voluntary act. Brain 106(3): 623–642.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Luper, S. 2009. The philosophy of death. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Margolis, J. 1975. Negativities: The limits of life. Columbus: Charles E. Merrill Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Minois, G. 1999. History of suicide: voluntary death in western culture. Baltimore: John Hopkins University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Muwahidi, A.A. 1989. Islamic perspectives on death and dying. In Perspectives on death and dying, ed. A. B et al., 38–54. Philadelphia: The Charles Press, Publishers Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Omipdam, B.A. 2013. Palliative care: An alternative to euthanasia. BMJ Support Palliat Care 3: 229.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Overall, C. 2003. Aging, death, and human longevity. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pereira, J. 2011. Legalizing euthanasia or assisted suicide: the illusion of safeguards and controls. Current Oncology 18(2): e38–e45.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Phipps, W.E. 1987. Death. Atlanta: John Knox Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prado, G.C. 2008. Choosing to die: elective death and multiculturalism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pritcher, G. 1970. ‘Intending’ and side effects. Journal of Philosophy 67: 659–668.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rachels, J. 1975. Active and passive euthanasia. The New England Journal of Medicine 292: 78–80.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. 1983. Intentionality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sidgwick, H. 1907. The method of ethics, 7th ed. London: Macmillian & Co. Ltd.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simon, O.R., et al. 2001. Characteristics of impulsive suicide attempts and attempters. Suicide and Life Threatening Behaviors 32(1 Suppl): 49–59.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Steffen, L., and D.R. Cooley. 2014. The ethics of death: Religious and philosophical perspectives in dialogue. Minneapolis: Fortress Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tong, R. 2000. Duty to Die. In Is there a duty to die?, ed. J.M. Humber, and R.F. Almeder, 133–158. Totowa: Humana Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Tooley, M. 1980. An irrelevant consideration: Killing versus letting die. In Killing and letting die, ed. Bonnie Steinbock, 56–62. Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Windt, P.Y. 1980. The concept of suicide. In suicide, ed. M.P. Battin, and D.J. Mayo, 39–47. New York: St. Martin’s Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Dennis R. Cooley .

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2015 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Cooley, D.R. (2015). Is There a Duty to Die?. In: Death’s Values and Obligations: A Pragmatic Framework. International Library of Ethics, Law, and the New Medicine, vol 62. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-7264-8_7

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics