Skip to main content

Pluralistic Theories of Absolute Obligation: Kant and Natural Law

  • Chapter
Meta-Ethics and Normative Ethics
  • 148 Accesses

Abstract

In this chapter I propose to consider two important theories — the Kantian and the Thomist natural law theory — according to which a number of principles of absolute obligation may be set out. I shall argue concerning each that the conclusions which are drawn do not follow from the premisses from which they are derived, and that even if they did, they would not be tenable.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. Although Kant’s clearest statement of this view is to be found in The Supposed Right to Tell Lies From Benevolent Motives, there can be no doubt that this is also the view of the Groundwork and of the Critique of Practical Reason.

    Google Scholar 

  2. The translations and numbering are those of H. J. Paton in The Categorical Imperative: London, Hutchinson, 1947: pp. 129–130.

    Google Scholar 

  3. See also The Metaphysical Principle of Virtue, 1st Part, Section 16.

    Google Scholar 

  4. H. J. Paton’s translation, The Moral Law, London, Hutchinson, 1948, p. 88.

    Google Scholar 

  5. The Moral Law, p. 89.

    Google Scholar 

  6. The Moral Law, p. 90.

    Google Scholar 

  7. See The Groundwork of the Metaphysic of Ethics in The Metaphysic of Ethics, translated by J. W. Semple: Edinburgh, Thomas Clarke, 1836: pp. 35–6.

    Google Scholar 

  8. I am here, for convenience, accepting Ross’s interpretation of the distinction between perfect and imperfect duties, but this is not essential to my general point, that Kant cannot establish the existence of duties which admit of no exceptions.

    Google Scholar 

  9. The Moral Law: p. 96.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Kant offers an argument which implies that all sexual behaviour, e.g. pre-marital kissing and other morally innocent conduct, is gravely wrong, as treating people as means and not as ends. His explanation as to why intercourse within marriage is not wrong is an ignoratio elenchi, being that in marriage each spouse gives him/herself wholly to the other and receives him/herself wholly back from the other in this reciprocal give and take. This has nothing whatsoever to do with the question. If it did, it would involve admitting, what Kant clearly wished to deny, namely, that permanent homosexual ‘marriages’ are morally permissible. Had Kant considered morally innocent marriages entered into by consenting adults without mutual affection, and purely for the purpose of using the other to reproduce, i.e. using the other simply as a means and not as a rational being, he would have seen that his theory leads to even more paradoxical conclusions. Clearly such conduct is not immoral, even though it may not be admirable.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Foundations of Ethics, Oxford, Clarendon, 1939, p. 173.

    Google Scholar 

  12. There is a suggestion of this view in G. E. M. Anscombe’s “Modern Moral Philosophy”, Philosophy, XXXIII, 1958, pp. 1–19. Many of the objections to be urged against the Thomist theory apply equally to Anscombe’s implied account.

    Google Scholar 

  13. D. G. Ritchie: Natural Rights, London, Allen & Unwin, 1894, pp. 38–41.

    Google Scholar 

  14. See Summa Theologiae, I, II, 94, esp. arts. 4, 5, 6.

    Google Scholar 

  15. J. Maritain: Man and The State: London, Hollis & Carter, (1st edition), 1954: p. 84.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Compare, for instance, his comments in reply to objections in Summa Theologiae, I, II, 94, 5 and I, II, 100, 1.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Compare K. Hörmann: An Introduction to Moral Theology: London, Burns Oates, 1961, with J. A. Ryan and F. J. Boland: Catholic Principles of Politics, New York, Macmillan, 1940: pp. 4–5.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Aquinas seems embarrassed by this apparent implication, namely, that only those who choose celibacy for spiritual reasons are morally justified. See Summa Theologiae, II, II, esp. art. 2.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Summa Theologiae, I, II, 94, 5, ad. 3.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Maritain seems to suggest this of world-wide institutions such as private property, but there seems no reason why his argument might not successfully be modified so as to apply to communities with different institutions. If he had looked more closely at the nature of the institutions of property, (and the different concepts of private property), Maritain may even have been led to the conclusion that each society develops those institutions, including marriage and family institutions, best suited for its members. Conservatives have often so argued in respect of property institutions. See Man and the State, p. 83 (1st Edition).

    Google Scholar 

  21. See Aquinas: Summa Theologiae, II, II, 64, 7; also P. J. Glenn: Ethics: St. Louis, Herder & Co., 1945: pp. 22–3.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Summa Theologiae, III, Suppl. 64.

    Google Scholar 

  23. For a thoughtful, sensitive, sympathetic approach to the morality of homosexuality which contrasts sharply with that of the natural law, resting as the former does on an examination of the facts and a concern for persons, see Iris Murdoch’s “The Moral Decision About Homosexuality”, Humanist, March, 1965, pp. 70–73.

    Google Scholar 

  24. See D. G. Ritchie: Natural Rights, London, Allen and Unwin, 1894, ch. 5.

    Google Scholar 

  25. See for example G. A. Kelly Birth Control and Catholics: London, Robert Hale, 1964: ch. 4.

    Google Scholar 

  26. The object of chewing gum is to have the pleasure of chewing whilst frustrating its purpose. With smoking, breathing is used to achieve the pleasure of smoking in such a way as partially to frustrate its natural end, that of bringing oxygen into the blood stream. By breathing in smoke instead of clean air the natural function of breathing is further interfered with by virtue of the damage done to the lungs. If this arbitrariness is eliminated, smoking, chewing gum, and the like must be condemned as being immoral, as immoral as using artificial methods of birth control. So, too, slimming biscuits must come under grave moral suspicion. This is plainly absurd.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1969 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

McCloskey, H.J. (1969). Pluralistic Theories of Absolute Obligation: Kant and Natural Law. In: Meta-Ethics and Normative Ethics. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-5065-3_8

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-5065-3_8

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-94-017-5067-7

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-017-5065-3

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics