Skip to main content

Sufficient Reason and Human Freedom in the Confessio Philosophi

  • Chapter
The Young Leibniz and his Philosophy (1646–76)

Abstract

This paper is concerned with certain features of what is perhaps one of the most important and interesting works of the young Leibniz. The work in question is a dialogue which he wrote during the early months of his stay in Paris — probably between Autumn 1672 and the early months of 1673 — and which he entitled Confessio Philosophi. Its theme1 is the justice of God, a topic which remained an abiding concern, culminating in the Theodicy of 1710. Here I shall be concerned with only a part of the dialogue, the part that concerns the question whether human beings can be called free.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. References, by page and line, are to the text of the Confessio Philosophi contained in A VI iii. Translations are my own.

    Google Scholar 

  2. For Leibniz’s approach to these problems, see G. H. R. Parkinson, Leibniz on Human Freedom (Wiesbaden: Franz Steiner, 1970), pp. 5–17.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Two common formulations of this principle are that there must be a sufficient reason for everything that exists and happens (e.g. to Clarke, 5.125, G VII 419; cf. Principles of Nature and of Grace, section 7, G VI 602; Monadology, section 32, G VI 612) and that there is no true proposition whose reason could not be seen by anyone who had all the knowledge necessary to understand it properly (Remarques sur le livre de l’origine du mal, section 14, G VI 413; cf. to Clarke, 5.125; Monadology, section 32, G VI 612).

    Google Scholar 

  4. Confessio philosophi 118, 2.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Confessio philosophi 118, 3–5.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Compare, for example, the remark that physics requires “the principle of the need for giving a reason” (Specimen Inventorum,G VII 309) with the assertion that it requires the “principle of the need for a sufficient reason” (to Clarke, 2.1, G VII 355).

    Google Scholar 

  7. Confessio philosophi 118, 9–10.

    Google Scholar 

  8. In Leibniz’s works, the principle of sufficient reason also takes the form of the assertion that there is nothing without a cause. It does not appear in this guise in the Confessio Philosophi; but see Catena Mirabilium Demonstrationum,12 Dec. 1676, A VI iii 584, and a paper on existence, Dec.? 1676, A VI iii 587: PDSR 113.

    Google Scholar 

  9. See also De Conatu et Motu, Sensu et Cogitatione (1671), A VI ü 283: “A requisite is that which, if it is not thought, something cannot be thought”.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Confessio philosophi 118, 9ff.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Confessio philosophi 118, 14.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Confessio philosophi 118, 15.

    Google Scholar 

  13. See also Demonstratio Propositionum Primarum, A VI ii 480: “I, as far as I know, was the first to demonstrate that the proposition that there is nothing without a reason is the foundation of the sciences of mind and motion”.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Confessio philosophi 118, 16–20.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Confessio philosophi 118, 20–22.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Elsewhere he argues for the principle of contradiction along similar lines. See PDSR xv-xvi, 48, 56; also to Foucher (1686), G I 382.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Compare Theodicy, section 44, G VI 127 and Remarques sur le livre de l’origine du mal, section 14, G VI 413.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Catena Mirabilium Demonstrationum, 12 Dec. 1676, A VI iii 584, PDSR 107; a paper on existence, Dec.? 1676, A VI iii 587, PDSR 111–3.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Remarques sur le livre de l’origine du mal, section 14, G VI 414.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Discourse on Metaphysics, section 13; to Arnauld, 14 July 1686, G II 56; De Verum a Falso Dignoscendi Criteriis (1685–7) G VII 301, VE 1174.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Confessio philosophi 118, 24ff.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Confessio philosophi 120, 16–9.

    Google Scholar 

  23. The Theologian says (120, 16), “You yourself have said”. This seems to be a reference to a remark made earlier by the Philosopher (118, 15), in which he concedes that philosophers seek a series of reasons until they reach a being which is necessary, i.e. is its own reason.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Confessio philosophi 120, 17.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Confessio philosophi 121, 4.

    Google Scholar 

  26. Confessio philosophi 129, 10.

    Google Scholar 

  27. See the definition of “author”, Confessio philosophi 127, 10.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Confessio philosophi 130, 9ff.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Confessio philosophi 131, 1; 131, 28–9. Confessio philosophi 132, 4.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Confessio philosophi 120, 3ff. Confessio philosophi 131, 17ff. Confessio philosophi 120, 4: cf. 131, 18.

    Google Scholar 

  31. Confessio philosophi 120, 4. Confessio philosophi 131, 19–20. Confessio philosophi 120, 5. Confessio philosophi 120, 7–9. Confessio philosophi 120, 10. Confessio philosophi 120, 11.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Confessio philosophi 131, 20–22.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Leibniz then elaborates on this, saying that the power and the will to sin come from the present state of things, and that in turn from the universal harmony and the immutable ideas contained in the divine intellect (131, 23–5). The point of this is to lead up to the assertion (131, 25) that there is no intervention of the divine will; God does not will sin, he only permits it.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Confessio philosophi 132, 4 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  35. Confessio philosophi 132, 8–9.

    Google Scholar 

  36. Confessio philosophi 133, 4 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  37. Confessio philosophi 132, 12.

    Google Scholar 

  38. Confessio philosophi 132, 12.

    Google Scholar 

  39. Confessio philosophi 120, 4.

    Google Scholar 

  40. As Leibniz notes (132, 13), this is a (slightly abridged) version of a definition given earlier in the dialogue (127, 8).

    Google Scholar 

  41. Confessio philosophi 132, 14.

    Google Scholar 

  42. Confessio philosophi 127, n.14.

    Google Scholar 

  43. Cf. Parkinson, Leibniz on Human Freedom, p. 18. For a fuller account of Leibniz’s concept of the will, see ibid, pp. 18–23.

    Google Scholar 

  44. Confessio philosophi 133, 13–4; cf. the beginning of Section VI below.

    Google Scholar 

  45. A VI iii 600, 6.

    Google Scholar 

  46. See Anthony Kenny, Aquinas on Mind (London: Routledge, 1993), p. 60. Kenny cites Aquinas, Summa Theologiae I, Qu. 80, Art. 2.

    Google Scholar 

  47. See Gilbert Ryle, The Concept of Mind (London: Hutchinson, 1949), p. 62.

    Google Scholar 

  48. One could say, indeed, that the Philosopher’s discussion of the will only emphasises the difficulties that lie in the way of free will. He argues (132, 14) that pleasure is a sensation of harmony, and that what is harmonious depends on the state of the percipient, of the object and of the medium. His conclusion (132, 21–2) is that we do not will to will — i.e. our acts of will are not in our power.

    Google Scholar 

  49. Confessio philosophi 132, 24–6.

    Google Scholar 

  50. Cf. Francesco Piro (ed.), G. W. Leibniz: Confessio Philosophi e altri scritti (Naples: Cronopio, 1992), p. 114, n. 24. Leibniz says only that the definition was stated by the “later Scholastics”. (Conversation with Stensen, 7 Dec. 1677, VE 302: C 25)

    Google Scholar 

  51. Confessio philosophi 132, 27–133, 4.

    Google Scholar 

  52. Confessio philosophi 133, 4–6. Cf. Leibniz’s conversation with Stensen, ibid

    Google Scholar 

  53. Confessio philosophi 133, 6–7.

    Google Scholar 

  54. Confessio philosophi 133, 8.

    Google Scholar 

  55. See Otto Saame (ed.), G. W. Leibniz: Confessio Philosophi (Frankfurt: Klostermann, 1967), pp. 173–4, notes 128–9.

    Google Scholar 

  56. E.g. Theodicy, section 34, G VI 122; section 301–2, G VI 296. On `spontaneity’ and `spontaneity with choice’, see also Parkinson, Leibniz on Human Freedom, pp. 57–8.

    Google Scholar 

  57. E.g. Theodicy, section 302, G VI 296; a paper on freedom (undated, but after 1676) G VII 108–9.

    Google Scholar 

  58. Theodicy, section 302; Causa Dei, section 20, G VI 441; Nouveaux Essais 2.21.9.

    Google Scholar 

  59. Theodicy, section 302; paper on freedom, G VII 108, 109; `Remarks on Descartes’ Principles’, G IV 362.

    Google Scholar 

  60. Confessio philosophi 120, 4–12.

    Google Scholar 

  61. Confessio philosophi 133, 9–12.

    Google Scholar 

  62. Cf. 135, 5: “The true root of freedom is the use of reason”.

    Google Scholar 

  63. Confessio philosophi 135, 14–6.

    Google Scholar 

  64. Confessio philosophi 135, 7.

    Google Scholar 

  65. Confessio philosophi 135, 14.

    Google Scholar 

  66. See especially a paper on freedom, G VII 109–10: “The more we act from the passions, the more we are slaves to the power of external things”. For other references, see Parkinson, Leibniz on Human Freedom, p. 63.

    Google Scholar 

  67. Affectus, 135, 10.

    Google Scholar 

  68. Much later, in the Nouveaux Essais (2.21.8), Leibniz was to recognise this as a kind of freedom, the `freedom to do’.

    Google Scholar 

  69. Confessio philosophi 133, 12.

    Google Scholar 

  70. Confessio philosophi 133, 13–4.

    Google Scholar 

  71. Confessio philosophi 133, 14–7.

    Google Scholar 

  72. Confessio philosophi 133, 17–9.

    Google Scholar 

  73. Confessio philosophi 133, 20–1.

    Google Scholar 

  74. Confessio philosophi 134, 1.

    Google Scholar 

  75. Confessio philosophi 134, 3–4. In connection with what Leibniz has said earlier, about willing as a kind of pleasure (cf. Section IV above), one may note that in the present passage pleasure is treated as a motive for an act of will, not as will itself.

    Google Scholar 

  76. Subtilis: 134, 7.

    Google Scholar 

  77. Nouveaux Essais, 2.1.15; Theodicy, section 305, G VI 297.

    Google Scholar 

  78. Confessio philosophi 134, 10.

    Google Scholar 

  79. Confessio philosophi 134, 10–11.

    Google Scholar 

  80. As has been said before, 134, 3–4.

    Google Scholar 

  81. Confessio philosophi 134, 12–13.

    Google Scholar 

  82. Confessio philosophi 134, 14–5.

    Google Scholar 

  83. Confessio philosophi 134, 15–6: quivisquod scit dicere potest, audiente quovis

    Google Scholar 

  84. Confessio philosophi 134, 19–22.

    Google Scholar 

  85. The existence of such a being has in fact been conceded at the beginning of the dialogue (116, 2, 10–11).

    Google Scholar 

  86. Metamorphoses, 7, 20–1, discussed in Confessio philosophi 134, 23. Cf. Theodicy, section 154, G VI 201 and section 297, G VI 292; also Nouveaux Essais 2.21.35.

    Google Scholar 

  87. Confessio philosopha 135, 1–2.

    Google Scholar 

  88. Confessio philosophi 133, 9–12; cf. Section V above.

    Google Scholar 

  89. Confessio philosophi 135, 5, 14–6.

    Google Scholar 

  90. Confessio philosophi 135, 16.

    Google Scholar 

  91. Confessio philosophi 135, 16–7.

    Google Scholar 

  92. Confessio philosophi 135, 17–8.

    Google Scholar 

  93. Confessio philosophi 135, 19–21.

    Google Scholar 

  94. Confessio philosophi 135, 23–4.

    Google Scholar 

  95. “Dic cur hic”, “Respice finem” and “Vide quid agas”. Such expressions are cited in works which are roughly contemporary with the Confessio: see Demonstratio Propositionum Primarum (1671–2), VI ii 482; Wilhelmus Pacidius (1671–2) A VI ii 511, G VII 362. Leibniz continued to cite them, e.g. `Remarks on Descartes’ Principles’ (1692), G IV 362; Nouveaux Essais, 2.21.47.

    Google Scholar 

  96. Confessio philosophi 136, 5.

    Google Scholar 

  97. Confessio philosophi 136, 5–7.

    Google Scholar 

  98. Confessiophilosophi 136, 10–12.

    Google Scholar 

  99. Confessio philosophi 135, 7, 14: cf. Section V.

    Google Scholar 

  100. Principles of Philosophy I 71–2 (The Philosophical Writings of Descartes, trans. Cottingham, Stoothoff and Murdoch, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1985, I 218–9); Replies to Sixth Objections, ibid. II 296–300. Leibniz could have added that, besides the circumstances of our temperament and upbringing, a cause of our use of principles which are not universal lies in the passions. These, it may be recalled, have previously been said (cf. Section V) to explain our failure to follow reason, and so be free. Leibniz could argue that the passions, which make us look to our own narrow interests, lead us to follow a perverted kind of reason.

    Google Scholar 

  101. Confessio philosophi 136, 12.

    Google Scholar 

  102. Confessio philosophi 136, 13–6.

    Google Scholar 

  103. Confessio philosophi 136, 16–7. In his notes on his conversation with Stensen of 7 Dec. 1677, Leibniz quotes this nearly verbatim: Gr 272, VE 301.

    Google Scholar 

  104. Compare the remark “The contrary implies a contradiction” (137, 26) which is made about the same thesis.

    Google Scholar 

  105. Confessio philosophi 136, 18.

    Google Scholar 

  106. Confessio philosophi 136, 21–9; 137, 1–8.

    Google Scholar 

  107. Confessio philosophi 136, 21–22.

    Google Scholar 

  108. Confessio philosophi 136, 26–7.

    Google Scholar 

  109. Confessio philosophi 136, 28.

    Google Scholar 

  110. Thomas Nagel, `Moral Luck’, in Mortal Questions (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1979), pp. 24–38, and Bernard Williams, `Moral Luck’ in Moral Luck (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981), pp. 20–39.

    Google Scholar 

  111. Nagel, op. cit, pp. 28, 32–3, 35. The other two sorts of moral luck recognised by Nagel are (a) luck in one’s circumstances, i.e. the kinds of problems and situations one faces (26, 33–4) and (b) luck in the way one’s actions turn out (pp. 2832). (E.g. a motorist might pass a red light, but by good luck there is no one on the crossing).

    Google Scholar 

  112. Confessio philosophi 137, 11–23.

    Google Scholar 

  113. Confessio philosophi 137, 23.

    Google Scholar 

  114. Confessio philosophi 137, 25–6.

    Google Scholar 

  115. Confessio philosophi 137, 26–138, 3.

    Google Scholar 

  116. The reference is to Confessio philosophi 136, 16–7.

    Google Scholar 

  117. Confessio philosophi 138, 1–3.

    Google Scholar 

  118. Confessio philosophi 138, 3–5.

    Google Scholar 

  119. Confessio philosophi 138, 5–6.

    Google Scholar 

  120. About 1670–71 (section 13: A VI i 542).

    Google Scholar 

  121. See also notes on three letters on Spinoza (October 1676?), A VI iii 368 n.16; conversation with Stensen, Gr 272, VE 301; Discourse on Metaphysics, section 30; Theodicy, section 264, G VI 274.

    Google Scholar 

  122. Confessio philosophi 133, 4–6: Section V.

    Google Scholar 

  123. Confessio philosophi 133, 13–4; Section VI.

    Google Scholar 

  124. Cf. Parkinson, Leibniz on Human Freedom, pp. 50–53. When Leibniz says that motives incline without necessitating, he is thinking of the strongest among two or more motives. The connection with hypothetical necessity is this: Whenever I make a choice, I follow the strongest motive. If, in the present situation, X is my strongest motive, then I follow X. The conclusion is necessary, but only hypothetically necessary, for it remains logically possible that I should have chosen something else. Had there been no such logical possibility, the conclusion would have been what Leibniz calls “absolutely necessary”.

    Google Scholar 

  125. Von der Allmacht and Allwissenheit Gottes, section 11.

    Google Scholar 

  126. There is a passing reference in 129, 24 and in a deleted passage, 127, note to 1. 16. Cf. 128, 8–9 and 129, 10 (per accidens necessarium).

    Google Scholar 

  127. Consider an example given by Stuart Hampshire, The Age of Reason (New York: Mentor, 1956), p. 167. Suppose that a householder, Jones, has been bound and gagged by a robber. As such, Jones cannot prevent the robbery of his house, i.e. it is necessary that he does not prevent it. This proposition is hypothetically necessary, i.e. it is necessary given that Jones is bound and gagged. Hampshire points out that it makes sense to suppose that the man could have prevented the robbery (in Leibniz’s terms, the proposition that he fails to do so is not absolutely necessary). But no one, says Hampshire, would suppose that such a man was free to prevent the robbery.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1999 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Parkinson, G.H.R. (1999). Sufficient Reason and Human Freedom in the Confessio Philosophi . In: Brown, S. (eds) The Young Leibniz and his Philosophy (1646–76). International Archives of the History of Ideas / Archives Internationales d’Histoire des Idées, vol 166. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-3507-0_10

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-3507-0_10

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-481-5332-9

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-017-3507-0

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics