Skip to main content

Foundational Aspects of Theories of Measurement

  • Chapter

Part of the book series: Synthese Library ((SYLI,volume 22))

Abstract

It is a scientific platitude that there can be neither precise control nor prediction of phenomena without measurement. Disciplines as diverse as cosmology and social psychology provide evidence that it is nearly useless to have an exactly formulated quantitative theory, if empirically feasible methods of measurement cannot be developed for a substantial portion of the quantitative concepts of the theory. Given a physical concept like that of mass or a psychological concept like that of habit strength, the point of a theory of measurement is to lay bare the structure of a collection of empirical relations which may be used to measure the characteristic of empirical phenomena-corresponding to the concept. Why a collection of relations? From an abstract standpoint, a set of empirical data consists of a collection of relations between specified objects. For example, data on the relative weights of a set of physical objects are easily represented by an ordering relation on the set; additional data, and a fortiori an additional relation, are needed to yield a satisfactory quantitative measurement of the masses of the objects.

Reprinted from The Journal of Symbolic Logic 23 (1958), 113–128. Written jointly with Dana Scott.

We would like to record here our indebtedness to Alfred Tarski, whose clear and precise formulation of the mathematical theory of models has greatly influenced our presentation (Tarski, 1954, 1955). Although our theories of measurement do not constitute special cases of the arithmetical classes of Tarski, the notions are closely related, and we have made use of results and methods from the theory of models.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   169.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. Although in most mathematical contexts imbeddability is defined in terms of isomorphism rather than homomorphism, for theories of measurement this is too restrictive. However, the notion of homomorphism used here is actually closely connected with isomorphic imbeddability and the facts are explained in detail in Section II.

    Google Scholar 

  2. In some contexts we shall say that the class K is a theory of measurement of type s relative to R. Notice that a consequence of this definition is that if K is a theory of measurement, then so is every subclass of K closed under isomorphism. Moreover, the class of all systems imbeddable in members of K is also a theory of measurement.

    Google Scholar 

  3. In this connection see Sierpinski (1934, Section 7, pp. 141ff.) in particular Proposition C75, where of course different terminology is used.

    Google Scholar 

  4. It is sufficient here to consider a relational system isomorphic to the ordering of the ordinals of the second number class or to the lexicographical ordering of all pairs of real numbers.

    Google Scholar 

  5. A simple ordering is imbeddable in Re, if and only if it contains a countable dense subset. For the exact formulation and a sketch of a proof, see Birkhoff (1948, pp. 31–32, Theorem 2).

    Google Scholar 

  6. The word ‘countable’ means at most denumerable, and it refers to the cardinality of the domains of the relational systems.

    Google Scholar 

  7. See Luce ( 1956, Section 2, p. 181). The axioms given here are actually a simplification of those given by Luce.

    Google Scholar 

  8. The authors are indebted to the referee for pointing out the work by Hailperin (1954), which suggested this general definition.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Te proofs of both these facts about H are very similar to the corresponding proofs in Suppes and Winet (1955; Article 8 in this volume).

    Google Scholar 

  10. Article 8 in this volume.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Essentially this example was first given in another context by Herman Rubin to show that a particular set of axioms is defective.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1969 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Suppes, P. (1969). Foundational Aspects of Theories of Measurement. In: Studies in the Methodology and Foundations of Science. Synthese Library, vol 22. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-3173-7_4

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-3173-7_4

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-481-8320-3

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-017-3173-7

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics