Skip to main content

Value-Based Ethics and Ethics of Rules

  • Chapter
Structure and Diversity

Part of the book series: Phaenomenologica ((PHAE,volume 141))

  • 169 Accesses

Abstract

In an earlier chapter, we noted that Christian thinkers in particular have taken exception to the apparent absence in Scheler of an ethics based upon moral rules. Some of this dismay may be based upon a misreading of Scheler’s intentions and, perhaps, to an underestimation of the power of Scheler’s value-ethics to support an ethics of norms. Yet one must concede that his theory is closer to a Classical model of virtue-ethics than to a Judeo-Christian rule-based ethics. Scheler states the point succinctly: The doctrine of virtue is prior to the doctrine of norms.67 Must we choose between these two kinds of moral theory, and, if we must, what are the conditions of the validity of such a choice? It would be interesting to reread Nietzsche’s Genealogy of Morals with the contrast in mind between the Jewish insistence upon a moral system that set forth the principled adherence to injunctions of the Torah even at the expense of human excellence (e.g., the Pharisees), and the Greek and Roman admiration of great individuals even despite their breach of moral injunctions (e.g., Alcibiades). For the Roman, the excellent man was not one who obeyed moral rules, nor for the Jew was the righteous man thereby excellent in the Roman sense of virtue. To use a modern expression, the two moral theories are incommensurable: the gap between them is one of ultimate and criterion-less moral principle, and is hence far wider than Nietzsche’s picture draws it. To him, one moral theory inspired scorn among the noble Romans and the other inspired ressentiment among the “impotent” Jews. The Jews, at least, appear to Nietzsche to have understood Roman values quite well, though they rejected them as vain. In Scheler’s view, the two theories are commensurable, although they are by no means equivalent or isomorphic. They simply represent different functionalizations of the same moral universe available to all persons. Yet although his moral theory judges actions with reference to values and not primarily to rules, and although he does not insist upon uncompromising adherence to moral law, as does Kant, his axiology provides ample space for a concept of moral norms.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. Der Formalismus in der Ethik,p. 50n.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Kant, in the famous passage that begins the Erster Abschnitt of the Grundlegung der Metaphysik der Sitten,appears to conflate nonmoral and moral goodness, for he compares directly the goodness of the Good Will with other things thought to be good, such as gifts of fortune and talents of the mind, noting the difference between them lies only in the consideration that the Good Will alone is an unqualified good.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Scheler traces his critique of Kant with reference to this point to Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit. Cf. Der Formalismus in der Ethik,p. 194: “Mit recht hat schon Hegel hervorgehoben, daß eine Ethik, die sich (wie jene Kants z.B.) auf den Begriff des Sollens, ja des Pflichtsollens gründet und in diesem Sollen das ethische Urphänomen erblickte, der tatsächlichen sittlichen Wertewelt nie gerecht werden kann, ja daß nach ihr in dem Maße, als ein bloßer Pflicht-Sollensinhalt real wird, also ein Imperativ, ein Gebot, eine Norm z.B. im Handeln auch erfüllt wird, der Inhalt aufhörte, ein `sittlicher Tatbestand

    Google Scholar 

  4. Der Formalismus in der Ethik, Gesammelte Werke,Band 2, p. 217.

    Google Scholar 

  5. G. W Leibniz, Political Writings. Ed. and trans. by Patrick Riley, 2nd ed. ( Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988 ), p. 83.

    Google Scholar 

  6. His observation, “all feelings of happiness and unhappiness have their foundation in feelings of values,and the deepest happiness and complete bliss are entirely dependent in their existence upon the consciousness of one’s own goodness,” is quite in keeping with his belief that values are prior to duties. Cf. Der Formalismus in der Ethik, Gesammelte Werke,Band 2, p. 359.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Der Formalismus in der Ethik, Gesammelte Werke Band 2, p. 214. Scheler uses the term “verdienstvoll” for what we have called acts of supererogation.

    Google Scholar 

  8. A.C. Graham, Disputers of the Tao: Philosophical Argument in Ancient China ( La Salle, IL: Open Court, 1989 ), p. 383.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1997 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Kelly, E. (1997). Value-Based Ethics and Ethics of Rules. In: Structure and Diversity. Phaenomenologica, vol 141. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-3099-0_8

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-3099-0_8

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-481-4827-1

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-017-3099-0

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics