Skip to main content

Description, Designation, Assertion: Russell, Jones and Bierich on Frege’s Semantics

  • Chapter
Sense and Reference in Frege’s Logic
  • 105 Accesses

Abstract

Having presented Frege’s reflections from ‘On Sense and Reference’, we now turn to the principal objections which the commentators have made against Frege’s semantics. This chapter will mainly deal with those critical positions which involve the bases of the Fregean analysis: other critiques which accept the bases but cast doubt on the application will be dealt with in the following chapters. In order to maintain clarity we will answer immediately upon presentation those critiques which are clearly based on a misunderstanding. Objections which can only be met on the basis of a more thorough study of Fregean texts are clearly formulated, and then answered in the second half of the chapter.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. Russell, B., ‘The Logical and Arithmetical Doctrines of Rege’, Appendix A in The Principles of Mathematics,London 1903 (2nd ed.: 1937), 475–496, resp. 501–522. References here to the second edition.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Russell, B. ‘On Denoting’, Mind,n. s. 14 (1905), 479–493.

    Google Scholar 

  3. The full quotation is: “According to the view I am espousing here, in ‘5>4’ or ‘2+3 =5’ one has to do only with expressions of truth-values, without anything having been asserted. This separation of the judgement from that which is judged seems unavoidable since a mere assumption or the positing of an instance, without deciding about its being the case, would be inexpressible” (FuB,21). - Even prior to the note in ‘On Denoting’, Russell indicated in his article ‘Meinong’s Theory of Complexes and Assumptions’ (Mind,n. s. 13 1904), similarities between the Fregean theory of sense and reference and Meinong’s theory of assumptions. Meinong, who had hitherto not been aware of Frege’s works (cf. Meinong, A., Über die Stellung der Gegenstandstheorie im System der Wissenschaften [On the Place of the Theory of Objects in the System of Sciences], Leipzig 1907, p. 4, n. 2), now thought he saw a similarity. In the second edition of his On Assumptions (Leipzig 1910, p. 6), he wrote: “If it ever happens - and much indicates that it should - that a history of the theory of assumptions is written, this will be in great part thanks to a sentence from Frege ‘s lecture on ‘Function and Concept’” (whereupon the above quotation is repeated). And, it seems that Wittgenstein took the expre scion ‘Fregean assumption’ from Russell. Cf. Notebooks 1914–1916 (edited by G.E.M. Anscombe, Oxford 1961, pp. 29 and 38); Philosophical Investigations, § 22 (pp. 10–11 in the Oxford edition of 1958); Tractatus,4.063. O.E.M. Anscombe (Mrs. Geach) was the first to draw attention to this misunderstanding (cf. An Introduction to Wittgenstein’s Tractatus,London 1959, 105–6, note).

    Google Scholar 

  4. Pr., 504, in this formulation. FuB,21, is inadvertently given as source.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Carnap, R. Meaning and Necessity. A Study in Semantics and Modal Logic,2nd ed., Chicago 1956 (1st ed.: 1947), 140.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Already in the ‘appendix’ of 1905, we find: “If we wish to speak of its meaning, we must use inverted commas or some such device” (pp. 27–28) (Pr.,502; the pages refer to SuB).

    Google Scholar 

  7. Already in the first lines of the article, what is conceived as the name of an expression appears once with, once without quotation marks. It is hard to see if Russell was confusing sign, sense, and reference or only sign and reference. Church is for the latter: “Russell’s reasons for rejecting Frege’s notion of sense are, in the reviewer’s opinion, without force. The point that some expressions, e.g., ‘the king of France in 1905’, have a sense but no designatum simply does not constitute a difficulty, except in the sense of a complicating factor in the construction of a formalized language. And Russell’s other objections, it would seem, are traceable merely to confusion between use and mention of expressions, of a sort which Frege is careful to avoid by the employment of quotation-marks. Russell applies quotation-marks to distinguish the sense of an expression from its denotation, but leaves himself without any notation for the expression itself; upon introduction of (say) a second kind of quotation-marks to signalize names of expressions, Russell’s objections to Frege completely vanish” (Church, A., Review of Carnap’s Introduction to Semantics, The Philosophical Review 52 (1943), 298–304; quotation from p. 302).

    Google Scholar 

  8. Jones, E.E.C., ‘Mr. Russell’s Objections to Frege’s Analysis of Propositions’, Mind, n. s. 19 (1910), 379–386.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Papst, op. cit.,28, with reference to the article mentioned in the previous note. Frege is also mentioned in Jones, E. E. C., ‘A New Law of Thought’ (Proc. Arist. Soc.,n. s. 11 (1911), 166–186). To judge by the article of 1910, the agreement involves aspects of the theory of sense and reference and, as the analysis in the text will show, the comparison should not be pushed too far. Papst’s affirmation about the influence of Frege on Jones will hardly bear scrutiny, since Jones’ ideas are to be found in the earlier work, Elements of Logic as a Science of Propositions,Edinburgh 1890, i.e., previous to the articles where Frege develops his second doctrine on judgement. As evidence, we offer the following quotation: “A significant Categorical Proposition, a Proposition in which the Predicate adds something to the Subject, may be defined as, A Proposition which affirms (or negates) Identity of Denotation in Diversity of Determination” (op. cit.,46).

    Google Scholar 

  10. In fact, according to Jones, Frege is of the mind that every affirmative proposition ‘S is P’ asserts the identity of S and P while the senses are simultaneously different. However, reservations are in order since Jones’ concept of reference does not seem to be that of Frege; cf. the equating of “denotation or application or applicability” (loc. cit.,382).

    Google Scholar 

  11. Papst, op. cit., 25, without sourcing. We could not find the text where Russell makes this objection. The problem is touched on in the introduction of the term ‘proper name’ by F. von Kutschera in Die Antinomien der Logik. Semantische Untersuchungen [Logical Antinomies. Semantic Investigations], Freiburg/Munchen 1964.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Example: “I call proper name or name of an object a sign which should designate an object” (Gg.,I, 43). Only an interpretation of ‘should’ in the sense that every proper name should be specified as the name of an object already known to exist (conventional ‘should’) corresponds to the view of the Basic Laws. This is our interpretation, but it does not suffice to eliminate the other view that the ‘should’ indicates that a proper name intends an object (intentional ‘should’).

    Google Scholar 

  13. Frege’s designation of ‘the greatest proper fraction’ as ‘senseless’ (Gl.,88 n.) does not contradict our interpretation. In a letter to Husserl, Frege says: “In the Foundations I had not yet made the distinction between sense and reference. In § 97 I would now put ‘referential’ instead of ‘senseful’. Elsewhere, too - e.g. in § 100, 101, 102 - I would in many instances put ‘reference’ for ‘sense“‘ (letter of May 24, 1891).

    Google Scholar 

  14. Hamburg 1951. Typed dissertation.

    Google Scholar 

  15. We are convinced that, on the basis of his presuppositions, Bierich was not obliged to carry out his proof of the correctness of Russell’s first objection in just this way. Since in Bierich’s interpretation of Frege an assertory sentence does not designate but asserts (or not only designates but also asserts), this is enough to make the relation between sentence and truth-value other than that between description and descriptional reference. In this case the relation between sentence and thought is not a genuine expressional relation and that between sentence and truth-value is not a genuine designational relation. Since this argument neither uses nor presupposes the concept of sense, the communication of the reference by the sense is of importance only for the special form of Bierich’s argument. But we do not recognize the presuppositions of either of these arguments and, a fortiori,of Bierich’s procedures of proof.

    Google Scholar 

  16. One looks in vain for a serious treatment of this theory in the commentaries. Granted Frege’s statements are easily misunderstood, this does not justify the superficial treatment that one finds. Even the recognition of Frege’s usage of ‘assertion’ — essential as it is for any critique — is sometimes missing Linke objects to the view that assertion is the declaration of a judgement: “It is clear that usage [!] contains assertions where the asserted is in no way held to be true, i.e., assertions which take place without and even against the conviction of the asserter. Every lie proves this“ (Linke, P. F., Was ist Logik?’ [What is Logic?], Wissenschaftliche Zeitschrift der Friedrich-SchillerUniversität Jena,3 (1953–54), Gesellschafts-u. sprachwissenschaftliche Reihe,Nr. 2/3, 179–190, here p. 184). All this says is that everyday usage knows as assertion a comportment which is not oriented toward the truth or falsity of the asserted. This does not refute Frege’s deviationist usage, where a false sentence cannot be asserted: “Since it is false, it cannot be expressed with assertory force” (Vern., 148). Cf. Geom., IV, 400: “For one who does not want to be fooled by words but wants to get to the bottom of things, word-usage by itself can decide nothing. One must always ask: is the word-usage in accordance with the thing?”

    Google Scholar 

  17. We are limiting ourselves to the German which Frege used, without prejudice to the validity of the above for other languages.

    Google Scholar 

  18. It is clear that only complete sentential questions are involved here.

    Google Scholar 

  19. A sign-series “I- (I- A)” would not be correctly constructed. And even this solution does not bring ultimate certainty. One could imagine the objections of a Wittgenstein: “But cannot someone in a stage-play write ‘I- A’ on a blackboard?” and would the “I- A” here not be without assertory force? A possible answer to this question is that “I- A” here stands in a context similar to that of expressions in indirect (e.g., quoted) discourse. But the described situation would have to be investigated further; and the objection itself is not without sophistication.

    Google Scholar 

  20. In this interpretation we have made extensive use of Fregean terminology. It would be better, in an independent presentation, to drop the expression ‘assertory sentence’, which can lead to misunderstanding, and to use a form of propositional sentence in opposition to interrogative, imperative, etc. sentences, with the complementary condition that only propositional sentences can be asserted. Whether a sentence is an assertion or not is decided from the context.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Geach, P.T., ‘Russell’s Theory of Descriptions’, Analysis 10 (1950), 84–88 (here p. 85).

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1968 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Thiel, C. (1968). Description, Designation, Assertion: Russell, Jones and Bierich on Frege’s Semantics. In: Sense and Reference in Frege’s Logic. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-2981-9_7

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-2981-9_7

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-481-8333-3

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-017-2981-9

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics