Skip to main content

Finding One’s Way about: High Windows, Narrow Chimneys, and Open Doors. Wittgenstein’s “Scepticism” and Philosophical Method

  • Chapter
Book cover Scepticism in the History of Philosophy

Abstract

In the so-called philosophical tradition from the beginning of Greek philosophy to the present time, we find different conceptions of philosophy; different ideas of what philosophy is, or should be. According to some, philosophy is very close to science; according to others, philosophy must be seen as having a practical objective; still others relate philosophy to mystical experience and religious belief. Perhaps the trouble with us today is that we sometimes ignore or blur this difference, calling “philosophy” what in the past was known by such terms as sophia, episteme,philosophia, prote philosophia, phronesis, dialectica, among others. I shall try to show here, that although to a certain extent in the Anglo-Saxon world, the conception that relates philosophy primarily to science and to epistemological problems has dominated for the past fifty years or so, Wittgenstein can be considered as defending a different conception, in which philosophy is closer to practical purposes and concerns, similar in many ways to classical scepticism.

Let us not pretend to doubt in philosophy what we do not doubt in our hearts. C. S. Peirce

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. See, for example, R. Watson, “Sextus and Wittgenstein,” Southern Journal of Philosophy 7.3 (1969): 229–236: J. Bogen, “Wittgenstein and Scepticism,” Philosophical Review 83 (1974): 364–373; A. Cohen, “Sextus Empiricus: Scepticism as a Therapy,” The Philosophical Forum 15. 4 (1984): 405–424.

    Google Scholar 

  2. For example, see J. Annas, “Doing without objective Values: Ancient and Modern Strategies,” in The Norms of Nature: Studies in Hellenistic Ethic, eds. M. Schofield and G. Striker ( New York: Cambridge University Press, 1986 ).

    Google Scholar 

  3. Some passages are particularly relevant in this respect: “The clarity we are aiming at is complete clarity. But this simply means that the philosophical problems should completely disappear. The real discovery is one that makes me capable of stopping doing philosophy when I want to” (L. Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations,3d ed. [Oxford: Blackwell, 1973], p. 133). Also: “The difficulty here is: to stop” (L. Wittgenstein, Zettel,2d ed. [Oxford: Blackwell, 1980], p. 314). See also Cohen, “Sextus Empiricus,” p. 419): “The anti-philosopher can do away with philosophy only by doing philosophy.”

    Google Scholar 

  4. SeeConversations with Druryin R. Rhees,Ludwig Wittgenste: Personal Recollections (Oxford: Blackwell, 1981).

    Google Scholar 

  5. In Rhees, Ludwig Wittgenstein.

    Google Scholar 

  6. See Sextus Empiricus: Outlines of Pyrrhonism (hereafter H.P.), in Works, trans. R. E. Bury, Loeb Library (London: Heinemann, 1976), I. Ch. 34.

    Google Scholar 

  7. I think this echoes Kant’s distinction between doctrine and critical inquiry: “Such a science must not be called a doctrine,but only a critique of pure reason”(I. Kant, The Critique of Pure Reason,trans. I. K. Abbott (Chicago: Encyclopedia Britannica, 1952), p. vii.

    Google Scholar 

  8. M. Williams, “Scepticism without Theory,” Review of Metaphysics 41. 3 (1988): 547–588.

    Google Scholar 

  9. H.P. I, 8.

    Google Scholar 

  10. L. Wittgenstein, Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus (London: Routledge, Kegan & Paul. 1974 ), 4. 112.

    Google Scholar 

  11. L. Wittgenstein, The Blue and Brown Books,2d ed. (Oxford: Blackwell, 1969), pp. 28, 62.

    Google Scholar 

  12. See Cohen, “Sextus Empiricus.”

    Google Scholar 

  13. Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations, § 133.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Ibid., § 109.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Ibid., § 124.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Ibid., § 144.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Ibid., § 123.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Ibid., § 111.

    Google Scholar 

  19. L. Wittgenstein, Vermischte Bemerkungen/Cutlure and Value ( Oxford: Blackwell, 1980 ), p. 44e.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations, p. 255.

    Google Scholar 

  21. N. Malcolm, “Conversations with Malcolm,” in Ludwig Wittgenstein: A Memoir ( Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1966 ), p. 51.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Wittgenstein,Philosophical Investigations,p. 309.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Wittgenstein, Vermischte Bemerkungen, p. 7.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Ibid., p. 27e.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations, § 89.

    Google Scholar 

  26. Ibid., § 129.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Wittgenstein, Blue and Brown Books, p. 44.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Adversus Ethicus. in Works, p. 165.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Wittgenstein, “Letter to Malcolm,” in Malcolm, Ludwig Wittgenstein, p. 39.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Remarks on the Foundations of Mathematics,eds. G. Anscombe et al. (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1956), p. 57.

    Google Scholar 

  31. Wittgenstein, Tractatus, 6.53.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations, § 133.

    Google Scholar 

  33. See Laércio Diógenes, Vida, doutrina e sentenças dos filósofos ilustres (Brasília: ed, UnB, 1988), pp. ix, 62; H.P. II, 246, 250, 254, 258.

    Google Scholar 

  34. H.P. II, 256.

    Google Scholar 

  35. Adv. Eth.,pp. 197–199, 210–215.

    Google Scholar 

  36. See, however, H.P. III, 280.

    Google Scholar 

  37. See C. Hookway, “Scepticism and Autonomy,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 90 (1989–1990); 103–118.

    Google Scholar 

  38. G. E. Moore, “Wittgenstein’s Lectures in 1930–33,” Mind 63.249 (1954): 5.

    Google Scholar 

  39. See T. R. Schatzki, “The Prescription Is Description: Wittgenstein’s Views of the Human Sciences,” in The Need for Interpretation, eds. S. Mitchell and M. Rosen ( London: The Athlone Press, 1983 ), pp. 120–121.

    Google Scholar 

  40. Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations, § 40.

    Google Scholar 

  41. Ibid., § 122. See Sextus’s criticism of the notions of definition (horos) and mental representation (nooumenon),as well as his attack on the traditional view of concepts (H.P. II, 227–228).

    Google Scholar 

  42. See N. Malcolm, Nothing Is Hidden (Oxford: Blackwell, 1986), Ch. 6.

    Google Scholar 

  43. “We want to replace wild conjectures and explanations by quiet weighing of linguistic facts” (Wittgenstein, Zettel,p. 447).

    Google Scholar 

  44. This suggestion comes from my colleague Professor Luìs Carlos Pereira.

    Google Scholar 

  45. His main targets seem to be his own “Tractarian semantics,” Frege’s conception of meaning, Russell’s theory of descriptions, and the “Augustinian picture” of language.

    Google Scholar 

  46. Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations, § 47.

    Google Scholar 

  47. See Malcolm, Nothing Is Hidden,Ch. 6.

    Google Scholar 

  48. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  49. See C. Guignon, “Philosophy after Wittgenstein and Heidegger,” Philosophy and Phenomenology Research 1.4 (1990): 651; Schatzki, “Prescription Is Description,” p. 119.

    Google Scholar 

  50. Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations, § 435.

    Google Scholar 

  51. Ibid., § 126.

    Google Scholar 

  52. RFM, p. 333.

    Google Scholar 

  53. L. Wittgenstein, Philosophical Grammar ( Oxford: Blackwell, 1974 ), pp. 210–211.

    Google Scholar 

  54. M. Burnyeat, “The Sceptic in His Place and Time,” in Philosophy in History, eds. R. Rorty, J. B. Schneewind, and Q. Skinner ( Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1984 ), p. 230.

    Google Scholar 

  55. H.P. II, 97–99.

    Google Scholar 

  56. Bumyeat, “The Sceptic.”

    Google Scholar 

  57. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  58. Ibid., p. 226.

    Google Scholar 

  59. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  60. Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations, § 124, quoted above.

    Google Scholar 

  61. Bumyeat, “The Sceptic,” p. 251.

    Google Scholar 

  62. Burnyeat, “Idealism and Greek Philosophy: What Descartes Saw and Berkeley Missed,” in Idealism: Past and Present, ed. G. Vesey ( Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1982 ), p. 42.

    Google Scholar 

  63. J. Lear, “Leaving the World Alone,” Journal of Philosophy (1982): 382–403.

    Google Scholar 

  64. Wittgenstein, Zettel, § 315.

    Google Scholar 

  65. Lear, “Leaving the World Alone,” p. 390.

    Google Scholar 

  66. Williams, “Scepticism without Theory,” p. 58.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1996 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

De Souza Filho, D.M. (1996). Finding One’s Way about: High Windows, Narrow Chimneys, and Open Doors. Wittgenstein’s “Scepticism” and Philosophical Method. In: Popkin, R.H. (eds) Scepticism in the History of Philosophy. International Archives of the History of Ideas / Archives Internationales d’Histoire des Idées, vol 145. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-2942-0_12

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-2942-0_12

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-481-4629-1

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-017-2942-0

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics