Skip to main content

A Formal Model of Ratio Decidendi

  • Chapter
Reasoning with Rules and Precedents
  • 186 Accesses

Abstract

Any complete account of legal analysis using precedents must include a model of ratio decidendi, the content of a precedent that is authoritative as to subsequent cases. Predicting, advocating, and justifying the binding effect of a precedent on subsequent cases all require identifying the authoritative elements of the precedent and showing how they can apply to subsequent cases involving different facts. Although the very existence of ratio decidendi is a disputed question among legal scholars, a functioning system of precedent rests on the assumption that some consensus can be reached concerning the the authoritative content of precedents (MacCormick, 1987) p. 157.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. This chapter includes material originally appearing in (Branting, 1994a).

    Google Scholar 

  2. See (Collier, 1988) for a detailed comparison of these two approaches.

    Google Scholar 

  3. The United States Supreme Court in Carroll v. Carroll’s Lessee,57 U.S. 128, 136, 16 How. 275, 286–287 (1853) similarly observed that “if [statements] go beyond the case, they may be respected, but ought not to control the judgment in a subsequent suit.”

    Google Scholar 

  4. A.C. 562 (1932).

    Google Scholar 

  5. For further discussion of the multiple levels of abstraction at which the holding of a case can be expressed, see (Stone, 1947) and (Stone, 1959).

    Google Scholar 

  6. Lew. C. C. 179 (1830).

    Google Scholar 

  7. Cox C. C. 163 (1883). L. R. 2 Ex. 259 (1867).

    Google Scholar 

  8. N.Y. 407, 14 N.E.2d 455 (1938).

    Google Scholar 

  9. N.Y. 288, 62 N.E.2d 74 (1945).

    Google Scholar 

  10. N.Y.2d 473, 473 N.Y.S. 743, 191 N.E.2d 279 (1963).

    Google Scholar 

  11. N.Y. 155, 124 N.E.2d 99 (1954).

    Google Scholar 

  12. N.Y.2d 554, 175 N.E.2d 441, 216 N.Y.S.2d 65 (1961).

    Google Scholar 

  13. N.Y.2d 34, 172 N.E.2d 526, 211 N.Y.D.2d 133 (1961).

    Google Scholar 

  14. This representation is also referred to as an AND/OR graph (Barr and Feigenbaum, 1982). In this particular graph, there are no OR branches, just AND branches.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Figure 3.2 is, in fact, a more detailed version of the right branch of the warrant-reduction graph shown in Figure 2.1.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Alternatively, the top-most warrant of the justification could be formulated as a biconditional, e.g., duty & breach & proximate cause IFF negligence. The warrant IF (no duty) or (no breach) or (no proximate cause) THEN negligence would follow directly from this biconditional. I believe that this approach is less satisfactory than an appeal to the closed-world assumption because there is often ambiguity concerning whether a rule is actually intended to be a conditional or a biconditional (Allen and Saxon, 1991). However, it should be noted that the use of the closed-world assumption in Figure 3.3 and in subsequent justifications in this chapter applies to rules rather than to domain propositions, as in more typical models of legal burden of proof, e.g.,(Farley and Freeman, 1995).

    Google Scholar 

  17. This warrant was expressed by the dissent in Palsgraf v. Long Island R.R. Co.,248 N.Y. 399, 162 N.E. 99 (1928).

    Google Scholar 

  18. U.S. 483 (1954). 27163 U.S. 537 (1896).

    Google Scholar 

  19. It has been noted that exemplar-based categories tend to be “hyper-polygons whose edges maintain equal `distance’ from nearest examples of different classes, where distance is measured by the system’s similarity metric. These boundaries are somewhat analogous to contours of zero potential between positive and negative electric charges in physical space” (Clark, 1988a).

    Google Scholar 

  20. An argument for the infeasibility of devising such a weighting scheme is made in (Ashley and Rissland, 1988).

    Google Scholar 

  21. A model of explicit choices among competing rules of decision is proposed in (Prakken and Sartor, 1998).

    Google Scholar 

  22. One description of the prototypes-and-deformations model suggests that it may be intended to apply to the explanations, as well as the facts, of precedents ( McCarty, 1991 ). This refinement would represent a departure from the simple exemplar-based approach and therefore from the applicability of Cross’s critique.

    Google Scholar 

  23. E. & B. 678 (1853).

    Google Scholar 

  24. The task of automatically generating plausible justifications to bridge gaps in the reasoning of precedents is a form of abduction (Pople, 1973).

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2000 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Branting, L.K. (2000). A Formal Model of Ratio Decidendi. In: Reasoning with Rules and Precedents. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-2848-5_3

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-2848-5_3

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-481-5374-9

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-017-2848-5

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics