Advertisement

On the Absence of Certain Quantifiers in Mohawk

  • Mark C. Baker
Part of the Studies in Linguistics and Philosophy book series (SLAP, volume 54)

Abstract

One characteristic of the Mohawk language1 from a comparative standpoint is that it does not have a set of quantified NPs found in English. In particular, Mohawk has no elements directly comparable to ‘everyone’ and ‘everything’, ‘nobody’ and ‘nothing’ — nominal elements which cannot be interpreted as referential. It will be suggested that this gap in Mohawk can be derived from general structural properties of the language. Mohawk is, in the terminology of Jelinek (1984), a “pronominal argument language”. In such languages, the relations among the parts of a sentence are established by pronominal coreference rather than by direct complementation. From this it follows that non-referential NPs are not allowed in such languages. The relevant principles must, however, be stated with some care so that they do not rule out similar structures which are found in Mohawk, including indefinite NPs, quantificational adverbs, sloppy identity constructions, and constituent questions.

Keywords

Relative Clause Argument Position Count Noun Plural Pronoun Null Pronoun 
These keywords were added by machine and not by the authors. This process is experimental and the keywords may be updated as the learning algorithm improves.

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. Baker, M. (1988) Incorporation: A Theory of Grammatical-Function Changing, University of Chicago Press, Chicago.Google Scholar
  2. Baker, M. (1990) Pronominal Inflection and the Morphology-Syntax Interface. In Proceedings of the 26th annual meeting of the Chicago Linguistics Society.Google Scholar
  3. Baker, M. (1991) On Some Subject-Object Non-Asymmetries in Mohawk, Natural Language and Linguistic Theory 9, 537–576.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Baker, M. (1992) Unmatched Chains and the Representation of Plural Pronouns, Natural Language Semantics 1, 33–74.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Baker, M. (to appear) The Polysynthesis Parameter,Oxford University Press, New York.Google Scholar
  6. Benger, J. (1990) Morphologically Bound Pronominals in Mohawk: Configurationality within the Verb Complex. Manuscript, University of Ottawa, Ottawa.Google Scholar
  7. Chomsky, N. (1981) Lectures on Government and Binding, Foris, Dordrecht.Google Scholar
  8. Chomsky, N. (1986) Knowledge of Language: Its Nature,Origins,and Use, Praeger, New York.Google Scholar
  9. Chomsky, N. (1992) A Minimalist Program for Linguistic Theory, MIT Occasional Papers in Linguistics, No. 1, MIT, Cambridge, Mass.Google Scholar
  10. Cinque, G. (1990) Types of A-bar Dependencies, MIT, Cambridge, Mass.Google Scholar
  11. Deering, N. and Delisle, H. (1976) Mohawk: A Teaching Grammar, Thunderbird Press, Kahnawake, Quebec.Google Scholar
  12. Hale, K. (1983) Warlpiri and the Grammar of Nonconfigurational Languages, Natural Language and Linguistic Theory 1, 5–49.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Heim, I. (1982) The Semantics of Definite and Indefinite Noun Phrases. Unpublished doctoral dissertation, University of Massachusetts, Amherst, Mass.Google Scholar
  14. Heim, I., Lasnik, H. and May, R. (1991) Reciprocity and Plurality, Linguistic Inquiry 22, 63–102.Google Scholar
  15. Huang, C.-T. J. (1982) Logical Relations in Chinese and the Theory of Grammar. Unpublished doctoral dissertation, MIT, Cambridge, Mass.Google Scholar
  16. Jelinek, E. (1984) Empty Categories, Case, and Configurationality, Natural Language and Linguistic Theory 2, 39–76.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Jelinek, E. (1989) The Case Split and Pronominal Arguments in Choctaw. In L. Mardcz and P. Muysken (eds.), Configurationality: The Typology of Asymmetries, Foris, Dordrecht.Google Scholar
  18. Kayne, R. (1975) French Syntax: The Transformational Cycle, MIT Press, Cambridge, Mass.Google Scholar
  19. Kayne, R. (1984) Connectedness and Binary Branching, Foris, Dordrecht.Google Scholar
  20. Koopman, H. and Sportiche, D. (1981) Variables and the Bijection Principle, The Linguistic Review 2, 139–160.Google Scholar
  21. Mithun, M. (1986) When Zero Isn’t There. In Proceedings of the 12th Annual Meeting of the Berkeley Linguistics Society, Berkeley, pp. 195–211.Google Scholar
  22. Mithun, M. (1987) Is Basic Word Order Universal? In R. Tomlin (ed.), Coherence and Grounding in Discourse. Benjamins, Amsterdam, pp. 281–328.Google Scholar
  23. Partee, B. (1973) Some Transformational Extensions of Montague Grammar, Journal of Philosophical Logic 2, 509–534.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Reinhart, T. (1983) Anaphora and Semantic Interpretation, University of Chicago Press, Chicago.Google Scholar
  25. Reinhart, T. (1987) Specifier and Operator Binding. In E. Reuland, and A. ter Meulen (eds.), The Representation of (In)Definiteness, MIT Press, Cambridge, Mass., pp. 130–167.Google Scholar
  26. Rizzi, L. (1986) On the Status of Subject Clitics in Romance. In O. Jaeggli and C. Silva Corvalan (eds.), Studies in Romance Linguistics, Foris, Dordrecht, pp. 391–419.Google Scholar
  27. Safir, K. (1984) Multiple Variable Binding, Linguistic Inquiry, 15, 603–638.Google Scholar
  28. Sag, I. (1976) Deletion and Logical Form. Unpublished doctoral dissertation, MIT, Cambridge, Mass.Google Scholar
  29. Speas, M. (1990) Phrase Structure in Natural Language, Kluwer, Dordrecht.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Vendler, Z. (1967) Linguistics in Philosophy, Cornell University Press, Ithaca, N.Y.Google Scholar
  31. Williams, E. (1977) Discourse and Logical Form, Linguistic Inquiry 8, 1.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 1995

Authors and Affiliations

  • Mark C. Baker
    • 1
  1. 1.McGill UniversityUSA

Personalised recommendations