Skip to main content

Biocentrism and Ecological Integrity

  • Chapter
  • 373 Accesses

Part of the book series: Environmental Science and Technology Library ((ENST,volume 13))

Abstract

It is difficult to be a biocentrist these days with all the criticism that has come their way. First of all, biocentrists are criticized for failing to state their view in such a way that it is not biased in favor of the human species.1 Secondly, they are criticized for following Ado Leopold and basing their view on an ecology that regards ecosystems as tending toward stability and harmony — an ecology that is now widely challenged with significant implications for the ideal of ecological integrity.2 Accordingly, one might think that it would be best, as critics have urged, to abandon biocentrism altogether in favor a hierarchical or anthropocentric view. In this paper, however, I show how biocentrism can be defended against these two criticisms and, therefore, should not be abandoned. Specifically, I do this by developing a set of environmental principles that 1) are clearly not biased in favor of human species, 2) can adjust to changes in ecological science and still pursue a goal of ecological integrity. If I am right that biocentrists can adequately defend themselves against their critics then the ethical demands of life would appear to be much stronger than many environmental philosophers have thought.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. French, W. 1995. Against Biospherical Egalitarianism. Environmental Ethics 17: 39–57.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  2. Shrader-Frechette, K. 1996. Individualism, Holis and Environmental Ethics. Ethics and the Environment 1: 55–69; N. Hettinger, Can Ecocentric Ethics Withstand Chaos in Ethics (forthcoming).

    Google Scholar 

  3. Mess, A. 1989. Ecology, Community and Lifestyle: An Outline of an Ecosophy (trans. David Rothenberg). Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp$1167–168. 4Ibid., p. 170.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Ibid., p. 170.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Taylor, P. 1986. Respect for Life. Princeton University Press, Princeton, p. 155.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Ibid., pp. 276–277.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Ibid. 1994. From Biocentric Individualism to Biocentric Pluralism. Environmental Ethics 17: 191–207; Reconciling Anthropocentric and Nonanthropocentric Environmental Ethics. Environmental Values, pp. 229–244.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Strictly speaking, not to treat humans as superior overall to other living beings is to treat them as either equal overall, or inferior overall, to other living beings, but I am using equal overall to include both of these possibilities, since neither possibility involves the domination of nonhuman nature, and, moreover, the latter possibility is an unlikely course of action for humans to take.

    Google Scholar 

  9. For a detailed discussion of this argument, see my article From Liberty to Welfare. Ethics (1994), pp. 64–98.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Moreover, this kind of fuzziness in the application of the distinction between basic and nonbasic needs is characteristic of the application of virtually all our classificatory concepts, and so is not an objection to its usefulness.

    Google Scholar 

  11. It is important to recognize here that we also have a strong obligation to prevent lifeboat cases from arising in the first place.

    Google Scholar 

  12. I add the qualification “normally” here because we know, for example, that humans sometimes enter into a relationship of reciprocal altruism with the members of other species such as dogs and horses.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Of course, libertarians have claimed that we can recognize that people have equal basic rights while, in fact, failing to meet, but not aggressing against, the basic needs of other human beings. However, I have argued in “From Liberty to Welfare” that this claim is mistaken.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Leopold, Aldo. 1949. A Sand County Almanac. Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Callicott, B. 1989. In Defense of the Land Ethic. University of Wisconsin Press, Madison, p. 58.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Botkin, D. 1990. Discordant Harmonies. Oxford University Press, New York; D. Ehrenfeld. 1992. Ecosystem Health and Ecological Theories. In Ecosystem Health, R. Costanza, B. Norton, and B. Haskell, eds. Island Press, Washington, DC; R.P. McIntosh. 1985. The Background of Ecology: Concepts and Theory. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Worster, D. 1990. The Ecology of Order and Chaos. Environmental History and Review, p. 13.

    Google Scholar 

  18. For the purposes of this paper, by “moral agent” I simply mean “agents that are capable of understanding and acting on principles like my environmental principles.”

    Google Scholar 

  19. To some extent, it was the difficulty ecologists had in specifying when ecosystems were in equilibrium that led them to endorse the ecology of disequilibrium.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Westra, L. 1994. An Environmental Proposal for Ethics: The Principle of Integrity. Rowman & Littlefield, Lanham, pp. 24–25.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Ibid., p. 108.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Similarly, Westra’s Principle of Integrity which prohibits harming the life support systems of the earth will normally operationalize into a requirement to protect this or that particular species.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Westra, L. 1995. Ecosystem Integrity and Sustainability: The Foundational Value of the Wild. In Perspectives on Ecological Integrity, L. Westra and J. Lemons, eds. Kluwer, p. 12.

    Google Scholar 

  24. See Old Age Insurance submitted to the Joint Economic Committee of the Congress of the United States in December 1967, p. 186; and Statistical Abstracts of the United States for 1986, p. 429.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Levitan, S. 1985. Programs in Aid of the Poor, 5th ed. Baltimore, pp. 1–5; D. Gordon. 1971. Trends in Poverty. In Problems in Political Economy: An Urban Perspective, D. Gordon, ed. Lexington, MA., pp. 297–298; A. Simon. 1975.Bread for the World, ch. 8.

    Google Scholar 

  26. Gendron, B. 1977. Technology and the Human Condition. New York, pp. 222–227.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Bergland, B. 1979. Attacking the Problem of World Hunger. The National Forum 69 (2): 4.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Sivard, R.L. World Military and Social Expenditures, p. 28.

    Google Scholar 

  29. For a discussion of these causal connections, see C. Silver. 1990. One Earth One Future. National Academy Press, Washington, DC; B. McKibben. 1989. The End of Nature. Anchor Books, New York; J. Leggett. (ed.). 1990. Global Warming. Oxford University Press, New York; L. Brown, (ed.). 1991. The World Watch Reader. Nelson, New York.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Successes in meeting the most basic needs of the poor in particular regions of developing countries (e.g., the Indian state of Kerala) should not blind us to the growing numbers of people living in conditions of absolute poverty, and how difficult it will be to meet the basic needs of all these people in a sustainable way that will allow future generations to have their basic needs met as well, especially when we reflect on the fact that the way we in the developed world are living is not sustainable at all!

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1998 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Sterba, J.P. (1998). Biocentrism and Ecological Integrity. In: Lemons, J., Westra, L., Goodland, R. (eds) Ecological Sustainability and Integrity: Concepts and Approaches. Environmental Science and Technology Library, vol 13. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-1337-5_5

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-1337-5_5

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-481-4980-3

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-017-1337-5

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics