Skip to main content

Carnap and the Unity of Science: 1921–1928

  • Chapter
Language, Truth and Knowledge

Part of the book series: Vienna Circle Institute Library [2003] ((VCIL,volume 2))

Abstract

In §179 of his 1928 Logical Structure of the World or Aufbau, Carnap notes that:

“We have repeatedly pointed out that the formation of the constructional system as a whole is the task of unified science, while construction theory is merely engaged in carrying out the appropriate logical investigations. By placing the objects of science in one unified constructional system, the different “sciences” are at the same time recognized as branches of the one science and are themselves brought into a system (§179).”1

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. Unless otherwise noted references are to sections of Rudolf Carnap, Der logische Aufbau der Welt. Hamburg: Felix Meiner 1928, subsequently published as Rudolf Carnap, The Logical Structure of the World & Pseudoproblems in Philosophy. R.A. George (Trans.), Berkeley: University of California Press 1967.

    Google Scholar 

  2. I follow Bullwinkle’s excellent dissertation (David S. Bullwinkle, Epistemology and Unity of Science in Carnap’s Aufbau, PhD thesis, Northwestern University 2000) in thinking of Carnap’s position as a moderate one. This work has been of great help for this paper more generally in understanding Carnap’s subtle views on the unity of science.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Bullwinkle, op. cit., p. 246. See pp. 246–255 for the argument. Bullwinkle cites Creath and Richardson as having given “undeveloped versions of this claim.” See Richard Creath, “The unity of science: Carnap, Neurath, and beyond,” in: Peter Galison and David J. Stump (eds.), The Disunity of Science: Boundaries, Contexts, and Power. Stanford University Press 1996, pp. 158–169 and Alan Richardson, Carnap’s Construction of the World: The Aufbau and the Emergence of Logical Empiricism. Cambridge University Press 1998, esp. pp. 37–40 & 183 – 184.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Heinrich Rickert, The Limits of Concept Formation in Natural Science. G. Oakes (ed. & trans.), abridged edition, Cambridge University Press 1986, pp. 38–39. Cited at Richardson, op. cit., pp. 37–38.

    Google Scholar 

  5. See, e.g. Michael Friedman, Reconsidering Logical Positivism. Cambridge University Press 1999, pp. 90–94.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Hermann Weyl, Space Time Matter. H.L. Brose (Trans.), 4th edition, Dover, New York, 1952.

    Google Scholar 

  7. See §57 for the argument that “it is in principle possible to reduce all psychological objects to physical objects.”

    Google Scholar 

  8. Rudolf Carnap, “Über die Abhängigkeit der Eigenschaften des Raumes von denen der Zeit,” in: Kant-Studien 30, 1925, pp. 331–345.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Rudolf Carnap, Abriss der Logistik. Vienna: Springer, 1929.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Hans Reichenbach, Axiomatik der relativistischen Raum-Zeit-Lehre. Braunschweig: Vieweg & Sohn, 1924, subsequently published as Hans Reichenbach, Axiomatization of the Theory of Relativity. M. Reichenbach (ed. & trans.), University of California Press: Berkeley, 1969.

    Google Scholar 

  11. I would like to thank Tom Ryckman for drawing this letter to my attention and for many helpful discussions about its significance.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Carnap to Reichenbach, June 20, 1923. Archives for Scientific Philosophy, Pittsburgh University, 016–28–11. “Es handelt sich um eine Strukturlehre der Weltlinien, oder in Ihrer Sprache: Axiomatik der Topologie der Zeit [...] Er verhält sich zu Ihrer Arbeit etwa, wie Russells Logik zur Mathematik, z.B. zur Arithmetik. Während die Ar. von Zahlen u. zwischen ihnen bestehenden Axiomen ausgeht, fängt R. weiter vor an: von rein log. Grundbegriffen und Axiomen ausgehend kommt man zu komplizierten Begriffen u. Lehrsätzen, die die Grundbegr. u.-sätze der Ar. bilden. So gehe ich von Axiomen (in zieml. grosser Zahl) aus, die nur Begriffe der Logik (besonders der Beziehungslehre) enthalten, u. gelange schliesslich zu komplizierten, abgeleiteten Sätzen, die (teilweise) Ihren Axiomen entsprechen.”

    Google Scholar 

  13. Archives for Scientific Philosophy, Pittsburgh University, RC 081–02–07.

    Google Scholar 

  14. “Eigenzeitbeziehung” is used in Carnap, Aufbau, op. cit., §62 and Carnap, Abriss, op. cit., p. 80: “Mit der (topologischen, maßfreien) Eigenzeitbeziehung xZy ist gemeint: x, y sind “genidentische” Weltpunkte, d.h. Weltpunkte derselben Weltlinie (Punktereignisse an demselben physikalischen Element), und zwar ist x zeitlich vor y.” However, the more awkward “Genidentitätszeitbeziehung” is used in the manuscript.

    Google Scholar 

  15. In §6 of the manuscript Carnap suggests that there are two possible interpretations for his symbols “K” and “Z “: 1) they are associated with non-logical relations or 2) they occur as variables in the axioms and these axioms are then associated with the appropriate physical relations. This is a problematic passage because Carnap seems to accept in the second reading something like Reichenbach’s coordinative definitions. I do not believe that this is what Carnap has in mind, though I cannot argue for this here. For a different interpretation of the significance of this passage see Don Howard, “Relativity, Eindeutigkeit, and Monomorphism: Rudolf Carnap and the Development of the Categoricity Concept in Formal Semantics,” in: R. Giere and A. Richardson (Eds.), Origins of Logical Empiricism. University of Minnesota Press 1996, pp. 115–164, esp. pp. 151–161.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Archives for Scientific Philosophy, Pittsburgh University, RC 081–02–07, p. 39.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Ibid., p. 41

    Google Scholar 

  18. Carnap, “Über die Abhängigkeit der Eigenschaften des Raumes von denen der Zeit,” op. cit.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Rudolf Carnap, Physikalische Begriffsbildung. Karlsruhe: G. Braun 1926.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Carnap, “Über die Abhängigkeit der Eigenschaften des Raumes von denen der Zeit,” op. cit., p. 334. “aus den topologischen Eigenschaften der Zeitordnung und der Koinzidenz können die topologischen Eigenschaften der Raumordnung abgeleitet werden. (Die weitergehende These, daß aus denselben Bestimmungen alle Eigenschaften der Raumordnung, also auch die metrischen, abgeleitet werden können, sei hier ohne Begründung oder weitere Erörterung nur vermerkt.)”

    Google Scholar 

  21. See Carnap, “Über die Abhängigkeit der Eigenschaften des Raumes von denen der Zeit,” op. cit., esp. pp. 343–345 for Carnap’s only published references to the Topologie manuscript and also for a reference to Reichenbach’s Axiomatization.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Carnap, Physikalische Begriffsbildung, op. cit., p. 16. “Alle Messung irgend einer Größe wird in der Physik auf Messung räumlicher Länge zurückgeführt [...]”.

    Google Scholar 

  23. In §16 Carnap remarks in passing that the two relations of the physical construction system “are uniquely [eindeutig] determined through the character of the schema.” This suggests that Carnap does not take these two relations as primitives. However, what he appears to have in mind is the possibility of eliminating these relations in the same kind of way that he claims that the basic relation of the psychological system can be eliminated. See §§153–155.1 do not think that either of these eliminations goes through, but I also do not think that they are a central part of Carnap’s project.

    Google Scholar 

  24. See Christian Thiel, “Carnap und die wissenschaftliche Philosophie der Erlanger Tagung 1923,” in: R. Haller and F. Stadler (eds.), Wien-Berlin-Prag: Der Aufstieg der Wissenschaftlichen Philosophie, Vienna: Hölder-Pichler-Tempsky 1993, pp. 175–187 and Rudolf Carnap, “Intellectual Autobiography,” in: P.A. Schilpp (ed.), The Philosophy of Rudolf Carnap, Cambridge University Press 1963 for more on this conference.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Reichenbach, Axiomatization of the Theory of Relativity, op. cit., p. xiii.

    Google Scholar 

  26. A review of Reichenbach’s publications during this period suggests that the subject of the talk was the connection between causal relations and temporal order as reflected in Hans Reichenbach, “The Causal Structure of the World and the Difference between Past and Future,” in: M. Reichenbach and R.S. Cohen (eds.), Selected Writings: 1909–1953, Vol. 2, D. Reidel: Dordrecht, 1978. This paper is closely connected to the 1924 book.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Reichenbach, Axiomatization of the Theory of Relativity, op. cit., p. 6.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Ibid., p. 8. See Hans Reichenbach, The Philosophy of Space and Time. M. Reichenbach (trans.), Dover: New York, 1958, I §4, esp. p. 14 for more discussion of coordinative definitions. There Reichenbach claims that “This coordination cannot be replaced by an explanation of meanings, it simply states that this concept is coordinated to this particular thing.”

    Google Scholar 

  29. Reichenbach, Axiomatization of the Theory of Relativity, op. cit., p. 9, Hans Reichenbach, The Theory of Relativity and A Priori Knowledge. M. Reichenbach (ed. & trans.), University of California Press: Berkeley, 1965, ch. IV

    Google Scholar 

  30. While Reichenbach and Schlick came to agree on these basic points, they disagreed on others. See Klaus Hentschel, “Die vergessene Rezension der ‘Allgemeinen Erkenntnislehre’ Moritz Schlicks durch Hans Reichenbach — ein Stück Philosophiegeschichte,” in: Erkenntnis 35, 1991, pp. 11–28, Hans Reichenbach, The Theory of Relativity and A Priori Knowledge, op. cit., p. 85, fn27, pp. 115–116, and Moritz Schlick, General Theory of Knowledge. A.E. Blumberg (trans.), 2nd edition, Open Court: La Salle, 1985, p. 384, fn48 (added in the second edition) for some evidence of this.

    Google Scholar 

  31. I would like to thank Tom Ryckman, Hans Sluga, Paolo Mancosu and Don Howard for their helpful comments and constant encouragement. Longer versions of this paper were presented at the Vienna Circle and Logical Empiricism conference and at the Vienna International Summer University in July of 2001. I would like to thank both audiences for their comments. The support of a Humanities Research Grant from U.C. Berkeley is gratefully acknowledged. All unpublished material is quoted by permission of the University of Pittsburgh. All rights reserved.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2003 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Pincock, C. (2003). Carnap and the Unity of Science: 1921–1928. In: Bonk, T. (eds) Language, Truth and Knowledge. Vienna Circle Institute Library [2003], vol 2. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-0151-8_6

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-0151-8_6

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-481-6258-1

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-017-0151-8

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics