Skip to main content

Elusive Body Boundaries and Individuality

  • Chapter
Prosthetic Bodies
  • 134 Accesses

Abstract

In the previous chapters I described a variety of mechanisms which have contribued to the emergence of fetuses and couples as patients and which have in part facilitated the development of IVF and fetal surgery. Arguments were presented to show that medical interventions n-define and relocate the problems addressed in ways that simultaneously transform the patients suffering from these medical problems. Precisely in doing all the medical work necessary to arrive at the particular diagnoses involved in fetal surgery and IVF for infertile men, new problem-definitions as well as new patients have been construed. Prior to artificial fertilization and modern prenatal technology, couples nor fetuses were considered to be patients as such.

“Of course, who controls the interpretation of bodily boundaries in medical hermeneutics is a major feminist issue.”256

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. Haraway (1991) p.169.

    Google Scholar 

  2. In the following quotes from feminist literature on the nature of modern medicine the theme of transparency of bodies is linked to visualization technologies, specifically ultrasound: “Since the seventeenth century, science has ”owned“ the study of the body and its disorders. This proprietorship has required that the body’s meanings be utterly transparent and accessible to the qualified specialist (aided by the appropriate methodology and technology) and utterly opaque to the patient herself.” Bordo (1993) p. 66;

    Google Scholar 

  3. Among the many transformations of reproductive situations is the medical one, where women’s bodies have boundaries newly permeable to both ‘visualization’ and ’intervention“’ Haraway (1991) p.169.; ”…take as an example the technique of echography, which allows you to externalize and see on a screen the inside of the womb and its foetal content. Offering “everything” for show, representing even the unrepresentable, i.e. the “origin”, means finding images that replace and dis-place the boundaries of space (inside/outside the mother’s body) and of time (before/after birth).“ Braidotti (1989) p.153.

    Google Scholar 

  4. See, for instance, Haraway (1985) p.169: “Such images [of fetuses] blur the boundary between foetus and baby; they reinforce the idea that the foetus’ identity as separate and autonomous from the mother (the ‘living, separate child’) exists from the start. Obstetrical technologies of visualization and electronic/surgical intervention thus disrupt the very definition, as traditionally understood, of ’inside’ and outside’ a woman’s body, of pregnancy as an ’interior’ experience. Increasingly, ’who controls the interpretation of bodily boundaries in medical hermeutics [becomes] a major feminist issue”; Petchesky writes that: “Like penetrating Cuban territory with reconnaissance satellites and Radio Marti, treating a foetus as if it were outside a woman’s body, because it can be viewed, is a political act.” (1987) p.65. For similar views see Duden (1993) and Franklin (1991).

    Google Scholar 

  5. Harrison (1982a) p.19. Quoted in Hubbard (1990) pp.175–76; in Bordo (1993) p.85; in Petchesky (1987) p.69.

    Google Scholar 

  6. This is, therefore, also an instance where Petchesky’s warning that we should not “confuse masculine rhetorics and fantasies with actual power relations, thereby submerging women’s own responses to reproductive situations in the dominant (and victimizing) masculine text” seems very much to the point (1987, p.71).

    Google Scholar 

  7. Harrison et al. (1993b) p.815.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Estes et al. (1992) p.951.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Estes et al. (1992) p.953.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Foucault (1979).

    Google Scholar 

  11. It is hardly trivial that the boundaries crossed are heavily laden with symbolical, cultural, and psychological meaning; these medical practices exist in cultures that simultaneously refer to genitals and wombs as “private parts” and “sanctuaries”. This inevitably creates tensions that women, quite unlike men, are expected to be able to deal with without complaint. Although such emotional and psychological acrobatics is in considerable measure required of all women in cultures that structurally medicalize the female reproductive body, it is hardly possible to imagine cases more extreme in this respect than the two technological practices of this study.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Hughes (1987) p.73.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Hughes (1987) p.53.

    Google Scholar 

  14. This also makes clear where I would depart from a systems approach in this case: unlike Hughes’s depiction of reverse salients, I would not take them to be empirically given, merely presenting themselves to the problem solver. Instead, their ‘identification’ is an active way of framing and locating a problem that is anything but neutral. It involves a specific attribution of technological failure, that always could have been different - one, moreover, that contains beforehand a legitimization of subsequent efforts to clear away this “barrier” to technical efficiency and success. It systematically leaves certain alternatives unexplored and assumptions unquestioned. It is, for instance, always in favor of continuation of experimentation and tends toward inclusion of whatever is designated as ’environment’ into the domain to be controlled and manipulated.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Adzick et al. (1993) p.810.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Harrison et al. (1993a) p.1415.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Harrison et al. (1993a) p.1413. Note how the military metaphor of ‘maneuvers’ in this quote affirms the appropriateness of ’reverse salients’ as analytical concept here.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Harrison et al. (1993a) p.1411.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Harrison et al. (1981), p.942.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Turner (1967).

    Google Scholar 

  21. The image of doctors as pioneers is often invoked to justify continued experimentation in the face of discouraging results. See for instance Michejda et al. (1986) p.881: ‘Thus the recent expression of disillusion with the long term benefits of antenatal treatment are premature. The concept is sound and justifiable, and the current problems are those common to pioneering efforts.“

    Google Scholar 

  22. Harrison’et al. (1993a) p.1414.

    Google Scholar 

  23. H. arrison et al. (1993a) p.1416.

    Google Scholar 

  24. H. arrison et al. (1993a) p.1414.

    Google Scholar 

  25. H. arrison et al. (1993a) p.1414.

    Google Scholar 

  26. Jennings et al. (1992) p.1332.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Jennings et al. (1992) p.1332.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Generally in this discourse, the whole range of medical care during pregnancy, and the specific forms of care in individual cases are commonly referred to as “fetal management”. Such care may involve, for example, having a woman travel to a clinic equipped with a neonatal intensive care unit, just before she gives birth to a child that is anticipated to need immediate surgery. In the context of ‘fetal management’, however, there is no woman making any trip, but a fetus being transported “in situ” (Harrison et al., 1981a).

    Google Scholar 

  29. See Casper (1995) p.73 for a similar observation about the role of the female body in the ‘fetal intensive care unit’ as planned, under this very name, in San Francisco.

    Google Scholar 

  30. The last three comparisons were made by a fetal surgeon of Guy’s Hospital, London, as quoted in a Dutch newspaper article. Van Zweeden (1990).

    Google Scholar 

  31. Harrison et al. (1993a) p.1411.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Harrison et al. (1981) p.939.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Touraine (1992) p.47.

    Google Scholar 

  34. H. allock (1985) p.787.

    Google Scholar 

  35. S. abik et al. (1993) p.547.

    Google Scholar 

  36. Sabik et al. (1993) p.547.

    Google Scholar 

  37. Haraway (1991) first introduced the metaphor of the “cyborg” in 1985 to capture the necessity of rethinking what can constitute embodied subjectivity in a way that takes the loss of the distinction mentioned into account.

    Google Scholar 

  38. The term ‘recognition’ does not necessarily imply that body boundaries exist prior to such recognition. Analogous to the recognition of new, self-declared independent states, and in the manner of speech acts, the act of recognition creates the reality of boundaries.

    Google Scholar 

  39. Rosoff (1981) p.3.

    Google Scholar 

  40. Rosoff (1981) p.1.

    Google Scholar 

  41. Rosoff (1981) p.1, quoting Justice Cardozo in Schloendorff v. Society of New York Hospital, 211 N.Y. 125, 105 N.E. 92, 93 (1914).

    Google Scholar 

  42. Palermo et al. (1992a) p.248.

    Google Scholar 

  43. Ng et al. (1991) p.1118.

    Google Scholar 

  44. Bals-Pratsch et al. (1992) p.101.

    Google Scholar 

  45. Two quotes from each paper cited, in which it can be seen that “patient” does not unequivocally refer to an individual at all: “There were two groups of patients: (1) Patients with very low sperm density on the day of oocyte retrieval, and (2) patients with 1-day-old oocytes that failed to fertilize.” “Seventeen couples completed the whole study. One couple (patient no.2) discontinued the study after three placebo cycles (…).”

    Google Scholar 

  46. Here we find the same hermaphrodite patients described in detail in chapter 2: the first quote has patients posessing both male and female gametes; the second shows a couple counting as one patient.

    Google Scholar 

  47. Robichaux et al. (1991) p.12

    Google Scholar 

  48. See chapter 2, section 3.2.

    Google Scholar 

  49. H. arrison et al. (1993a) p.1413.

    Google Scholar 

  50. C. rombleholme et al. (1988) p.1115.

    Google Scholar 

  51. A. ppelman and Golbus (1986) p.487.

    Google Scholar 

  52. T. ouraine (1992) p.45.

    Google Scholar 

  53. B. als-Pratsch et al. (1992) p.103.

    Google Scholar 

  54. R. obertson (1986) p.603.

    Google Scholar 

  55. G. oldstein et al. (1990) p.89.

    Google Scholar 

  56. K. older et al. (1988).

    Google Scholar 

  57. See for such opposition, for example, Annas (1986), (1987); Nelson and Milliken (1988); Fletcher (1986); Pringle (1986), and Purdy (1999).

    Google Scholar 

  58. Engelhardt (1985) p. 315.

    Google Scholar 

  59. E. ngelhardt (1985) p.315.

    Google Scholar 

  60. Robertson (1986) p.608.

    Google Scholar 

  61. A. merican Academy of Pediatrics (1988) p.899.

    Google Scholar 

  62. American Academy of Pediatrics (1988) p.899.

    Google Scholar 

  63. American Academy of Pediatrics (1988) p.899.

    Google Scholar 

  64. And, ironically, so is the number of women willing to act as guinee pigs so that ‘experimental’ procedures may eventually become ‘established’.

    Google Scholar 

  65. Smith (1985) p.380.

    Google Scholar 

  66. Spielman (1984) p.759.

    Google Scholar 

  67. Engelhardt (1985) p.313.

    Google Scholar 

  68. Engelhardt (1985) p.316. The ‘cases’ referred to in this quote are court-cases, which renders the choice of words (’tolerating’ when the woman’s basic rights were not overruled; ’inviting’ for court-ordered surgical intervention) particularly inappropriate.

    Google Scholar 

  69. Goldstein et al. (1990) p.87.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2001 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

van der Ploeg, I. (2001). Elusive Body Boundaries and Individuality. In: Prosthetic Bodies. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-9847-7_5

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-9847-7_5

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-481-5866-9

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-015-9847-7

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics