Skip to main content

Somes Notes on the History of Taxation

  • Chapter
Justifying Taxes

Part of the book series: Law and Philosophy Library ((LAPS,volume 51))

  • 191 Accesses

Abstract

This chapter aims at providing a minimal historical background to the present research. It does not pretend to be exhaustive. All that is said is based on secondary sources, providing only a taste of the literature on the matter. Notwithstanding such limitations, some notes on the history of taxation might be necessary to our enterprise. In positive terms, it renders clear that taxation is a mental artefact. Taxes are not hard facts belonging to the empirical realm, but political inst itut ions, creatures of the in-between individuals that is politics1. As it is the case with other institutional facts, they only have a temporal dimension2. Consequently, its emergence as a social institution can be dated, and its evolution can be structured in different period according to the general principles that regulated the institution. In negative terms, it provides us with the elements needs in order to challenge the arguments of doom of historical determinism.

“History does not teach much, but still teaches considerably more than social-science theories”

Hannah Arendt Civil Disobedience

“It is a pity but some other word beside taxation had been devised for so noble and extraordinary an occasion, as the protection of liberty and the establishment of an independent world. We have given to a popular subject an unpopular name, and injured the service by a wrong assemblage of ideas”

Thomas Paine The Necessity of Taxation

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 169.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. Arendt (1997, 45).

    Google Scholar 

  2. Weinberger in MacCormick and Weinberger (1986, 38).

    Google Scholar 

  3. See §§ 15–24.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Habermas (1996b, 771). The paramount role played by the legal paradigm in legal education has been explored in Anglo-American legal theory. See MacCormick (1978, 122), Dworkin (1986, 10, 87–9, 245, 265) and Bell (1986, 46–9).

    Google Scholar 

  5. See § §298ff.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Touzery (1998, 45–6).

    Google Scholar 

  7. See §§ 15–24.

    Google Scholar 

  8. On the concept of the tax state, opposed to the fiscal state, see Schumpeter (1954b).

    Google Scholar 

  9. Karl Polanyi has made it clear that the market economy is a rare structure in economic history. See Polanyi (1977).

    Google Scholar 

  10. Tilly (1996, 50).

    Google Scholar 

  11. Finley (1991, 32) refers to the fact that this strengthened internal cohesion, as it allowed rulers to purchase legitimacy by means of somehow distributing the product of confiscation.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Tilly (1992, 96–7) and Ormrod and Barta (1995, 72).

    Google Scholar 

  13. Of course, the focus on classical Greece and Rome reflects the tendency to marginalise other political communities. But silence seems preferable to rely on quite fragmentary and either orientalising or unsound sources. On the risks of orientalising, see Said (1978).

    Google Scholar 

  14. Nozick (1974, 169).

    Google Scholar 

  15. Meiksins Wood (1994, 83–6).

    Google Scholar 

  16. This hypothesis is confirmed by the fact that the discharge of public offices was compensated with a per diem payment. This has been interpreted as evidence of the fact that Athens was composed by a massive class of passive citizens, who lived on the surplus obtained from slavery. However, payments were very modest, and seem to have been intended in order to ensure citizens (especially peasants) that even in rough times they will have some income and could avoid private patronage. See Finley (1991 34).

    Google Scholar 

  17. Finley (1991, 33).

    Google Scholar 

  18. Ardant (1971).

    Google Scholar 

  19. Sainz de Bujanda (1962b, 162).

    Google Scholar 

  20. Van Caenegem (1995, 36).

    Google Scholar 

  21. Ricca Salerno (1960, 12) and Sainz de Bujanda (1962b, 213–20).

    Google Scholar 

  22. This paragraph is mainly based in Oakley (1980).

    Google Scholar 

  23. Bartlett (1993, chapter 3).

    Google Scholar 

  24. Bartlett (1993, 80).

    Google Scholar 

  25. Ricca Salerno (1960, 12).

    Google Scholar 

  26. See Bodin (1977, book I, chapter X).

    Google Scholar 

  27. Molho (1971).

    Google Scholar 

  28. This seems to have been, unsurprisingly, a Dutch innovation. See ‘t Hart (1990).

    Google Scholar 

  29. Cf. Groves (1974, 13) and Touzery (1998, 24ff).

    Google Scholar 

  30. Cf. García de Enterría (1994, especially 34–42).

    Google Scholar 

  31. Cf. Kant (1996, 467). Cf. Otis (1764).

    Google Scholar 

  32. Cf. Escribano (1989), who argues that in the first Spanish liberal constitution we can see a distinction between the general legislative power and the power to tax.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Cf. Sièyes (1989, 57): “Les lois, qui devraient au moins être exemples de partialité, se montrent ellesmêmes complices des privilèges”.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Cf. Sièyes (1989, 56): “Nous attendons, de votre part, un acte d’obéissance à la loi commune, plutôt que vous avez si longtemps traité sons pitié”.

    Google Scholar 

  35. Cf. Sièves (1989, 57).

    Google Scholar 

  36. Cf. Gauchet (1989), Skinner (1998).

    Google Scholar 

  37. This is something that can be hinted at even in the work of authors like Hume and Adam Smith, and that is very clear in the work of Thomas Paine or in the program of the Jacobins in France

    Google Scholar 

  38. Smith (1976, book 1, chapter 2).

    Google Scholar 

  39. This leaves open a certain ambiguity in Smith’s argument on the basis of which it has been argued that he did not constitute a pure case of liberism.

    Google Scholar 

  40. Cf. Spencer (1994, 131): “The beneficial results of the survival of the fittest, prove to be immeasurably greater than those above indicated [basically, the provision of welfare benefits to the poor]. The process of ‘natural selection, as Mr Darwin called it, co-operating with a tendency to variation and to inheritance of variations, has shown to be a chief cause (though not, I believe, the sole cause) of that evolution through which all living things, beginning with the lowest and diverging and re-diverging as they evolved, have reached their present degrees of organisation and adaptation to their modes of life”. Spencer is a fascinating writer because he anticipated all arguments of liberists. A contemporary reader will be surprised by his pioneering analysis of unforeseen consequences of intentional action (Spencer, 1994, 94), his reliance on charity as a more adequate means of providing for the poor (Spencer, 1994, 128) or his reference to the undeserving poor.

    Google Scholar 

  41. Bruguière (1988).

    Google Scholar 

  42. Cf. the Guide des Citoyens dans l’évaluation du quart de leurs revenus pour la contribution patriotique, Chez Le Clere, Paris, November 1789. The pamphlet is included in the Kress Microfilm Collection, item 13961.4. The pamphlet is a dialogue written in a similar spirit to the leaflets produced by modern tax administrations in order to calculate the Income Tax.

    Google Scholar 

  43. Cf. Instruction publiée par ordre du Roi relativement à la contribution patriotique, Imprimeries de B Gibelin-David., Aix, available in the Kress collection, item 13961.8, which includes appended forms.

    Google Scholar 

  44. For example, the American Revolutionaries had to pay for the Independence War, at one time had no other choice than to issue paper money that was repudiated latter on. Similarly, financing war led French Revolutionaries to impose forced loans on the population.

    Google Scholar 

  45. See Hinrichs (1966).

    Google Scholar 

  46. Neumark (1974, 62–5).

    Google Scholar 

  47. This explains why the conceptualisation of taxes proceeded by means of importing concepts from private law. For example, this explains why the obligation to pay taxes was seen as an instance of the general category of obligation in private law.

    Google Scholar 

  48. Frison-Roche (1997, 199). Public debt is just a mechanism for spending now the taxes that will be collected afterwards.

    Google Scholar 

  49. This idea was echoed many years later by Spooner (1869, at the end of chapter III): “That the only security men can have for their political liberty, consists in their keeping their money in their won pockets, until they have assurances, perfectly satisfactory to themselves, that it will be used as they wish it to be used, for their benefit, and not for their injury”.

    Google Scholar 

  50. De Viti de Marco (1928, 97): “[U]na quota parte del reddito dei cittadini, che lo Stato preleva per procurarsi i mezzi necessari alla produzioni dei servizi pubblici generali”

    Google Scholar 

  51. Berliri (1945, 343): “[Q]uota individuale di un debito comune e divisibile”.

    Google Scholar 

  52. Griziotti (1929, 150).

    Google Scholar 

  53. Puviani (1901, 15 and 16), translation taken from Puviani (1993, 45–6 and 46): “the definition of ends which were to be attained by means of taxation was not regarded as falling within the realm of the individual or the conscience. Like the government, it looked as though these ends had a particular sphere of activity assigned to them by nature itself (...) in the period of highest exaltation of the individual (...) the individual appears as an element which is not conscious of the great results of his own work”.

    Google Scholar 

  54. Of course, not everybody agreed. Thomas Paine, who had become a French citizen and a Girondin delegate, expressed the arguments against such move in his speech to the National Convention on July 1795: “I might here ask, if those only who come under the above description are to be considered as citizens, what designation do you mean to give the rest of the people?” C f. Paine (1795. 25).

    Google Scholar 

  55. The Constitution of Pennsylvania (1776) seems to have been the first to use taxpaying as the criterion to confer voting rights. section 6: “Every freeman of the full age of twenty-one years, having resided in this state for the space of one whole year next before the day of election for representatives, and paid public taxes during that time, shall enjoy the right of an elector: Provided always that sons of freeholders of the age of twenty-one years shall be intitled to vote although they have not paid taxes”

    Google Scholar 

  56. Cf. Heller (1985, 288).

    Google Scholar 

  57. Mayer (1950, 192).

    Google Scholar 

  58. See Rodríguez Bereijo (1979).

    Google Scholar 

  59. Polanyi (1944). For the American case, see Fiss (1993).

    Google Scholar 

  60. Habermas (1996b, 773). See Fiss (1987)

    Google Scholar 

  61. Habermas (1996a, 408).

    Google Scholar 

  62. Cf. Schumpeter (1954a, 202): “Everything that happens in the political sphere reflects itself in the ideas about fiscal policy”.

    Google Scholar 

  63. Milward (1981, 63 and 65): “The imperfect mechanisms of incomplete democracies made the tariff books seem as important an expression of the political balance of the nation as the Constitution. They represented written compromises on real tests of political as well as economic strengh. Hence the extraordinary importance of tariffs in public argument when non-tariff barriers were probably, as now, much more important in regulating and obstructing international trade”

    Google Scholar 

  64. Musgrave (1995). See also Backhaus (1997).

    Google Scholar 

  65. Originally contained in Wagner Die Ordnung des österreichischen Staatshaushalts. 1863., published in 1864 in Vienna, quoted from Backhaus (1997, 267)

    Google Scholar 

  66. The classic statement is, of course, Keynes (1936).

    Google Scholar 

  67. Steinmo (1993).

    Google Scholar 

  68. Of course, there are always dissenting voices. Among those, we can find partisans of the old formal paradigm of law and the relationship between it and the economic system, like Friedrich von Hayek.

    Google Scholar 

  69. Offe (1996, 153–9) describes this institutional logic.

    Google Scholar 

  70. This is expressed in relative terms, or what is the same, compared to the total size of the economy.

    Google Scholar 

  71. Two main methods have been employed in economic literature, the so-called currency method and the model approach. The former assumes that shadow transactions are undertaken in the form of cash payments, thus leaving no trace. An increase in the size of the shadow economy will therefore increase the demand for currency. Further calculations are needed in order to make more precise the estimation, including the discount of conventional factors which increase currency demand and contrasting it with potential causes of increase of the informal economy (direct and indirect tax burden, transparency of the tax system, state regulation). The latter assumes that a set of variables serve as the indicators of the size of the shadow economy. However, both methods are open to criticism. The two of them have a hard time including factors like the perception of fairness in design and justice in operation of the tax system by taxpayers. See Schneider (1997, 6): “Other reasons -such as the impact of regulation, the complexity or visibility of the tax system, taxpayers’ attitude to the state, tax morality’ and so on- are not considered because data for most countries are not available. Additionally, detailed empirical findings are often of a confidential nature. See (Tanzi and Parthasarathi, 1993, 3). That might be explained, among other reasons because publicising detailed results might warn tax evaders of future monitoring action on the side of the tax administration and might also further erode the trust of the average citizen on the fairness of the tax system.

    Google Scholar 

  72. The shadow, informal or black economy refers to “all those perfectly legitimate activities, resulting in transactions (in kind or for payment) between individuals, which are (...) hidden from the authorities, principally the tax authorities”, in Pyle (1989, 3). For the size of the shadow economy, see Table 1. The shadow economy has grown at three times the speed of the official one since the 60’s. Cf. The Economist, 3 May 1997.

    Google Scholar 

  73. The overall level of tax fraud tends to be calculated by reference to the size of the shadow economy. Other sources of information concerning its size could be partial estimates of the tax administration concerning fraud on specific taxes (like excise taxation) or the counter-intuitive data on average income of different professional activities according to reported income. For example, in Italy and Spain, the average income of a liberal professional is lower or slightly higher than that of an unqualified employee, according to their income report. That goes against common experience and any serious estimation, pointing to considerable and widespread tax fraud. OLAF, the Antifraud Unit of the European Union, has estimated the levels of tax evasion associated with tobacco smuggling around 4.4000 million euro. See Financial Times, EU to sue Us tobacco groups, 21 July, 2000 and the complaint filed before the US District Court for the Eastern District of New York in the case The European Community v.RJRNabisco et al, available at http://www.nyed.uscourts.gov/pub/ruli ngs/cv/2000/00cv6617cmp.pdf.

    Google Scholar 

  74. This is more threatening than widespread public opposition to the tax system. Even most forms of civil disobedience are less problematic, because they challenge the prevailing political conception but at the same time point to an alternative one on the basis of which it is possible to structure social relationships. Cf. Arendt (1972). The threat to stability posed by disobedient citizens is to be blamed on the abuses of political authorities that force individuals to make use of this measure of last resort. On this, see Rawls (1969, 255).

    Google Scholar 

  75. Medlan (1984). 76 Cf. §75.

    Google Scholar 

  76. Medlan (1984).

    Google Scholar 

  77. Cf. §75.

    Google Scholar 

  78. Genschel (1999, 4).

    Google Scholar 

  79. Offe (1996, 118).

    Google Scholar 

  80. Habermas (1973, 101).

    Google Scholar 

  81. According to Eurostat, taxes on employed labour were 43.2% of total tax revenue in 1970 and 51.4, almost eight points more, in 1995.

    Google Scholar 

  82. Cf. §§183ff.

    Google Scholar 

  83. For a criticism, see Eisenstein (1961, chapter 5). The trend seems unstoppable. Recent examples are Spain (Decree-Law 6/1996, of June 7th, on Tax Measures) and the UK (Prudent for a purpose: working for a stronger and fairer Britain, in which the Chancellor of the Exchequer, Mr. Brown, announces that capital gains tax for business assets will go down to 10% in four years).

    Google Scholar 

  84. See OECD (1998). Cf. §197.

    Google Scholar 

  85. Cf. Tobin (1978), Tobin (1994). A good deal of bibliographical references and reports on political initiatives to implement the Tobin tax can be found at http://www.tobintax.org

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2001 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Menéndez, A.J. (2001). Somes Notes on the History of Taxation. In: Justifying Taxes. Law and Philosophy Library, vol 51. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-9825-5_3

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-9825-5_3

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-481-5726-6

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-015-9825-5

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics