Advertisement

The Hypothetico-Deductive Model of Scientific Theories: A Sympathetic Disclaimer

  • Graham Solomon
Chapter
  • 123 Downloads
Part of the The Western Ontario Series in Philosophy of Science book series (WONS, volume 65)

Abstract

The major philosophical points I wish to make in this essay are not fully original, although I hope that what I have to say makes a coherent and persuasive whole. I shall be discussing a predominating philosophy of science that has held the field against most other systematic philosophies of science for at least five decades. Sometimes this philosophy has been called “Neo-Positivism,” (in part to distinguish it from the nineteenth-century positivism of Comte) sometimes, “Logical Empiricism.” It shares much with the early “Logical Positivism” of Schlick and other members of the Vienna Circle — a sophisticated philosophical position not to be confused with the positivism of Ayer’s shallow Language, Truth and Logic — but for many advocates the historical roots lie elsewhere. The labels are not that important, especially since every essential ingredient of the philosophy of science I shall be discussing is to be found in much earlier, diverse philosophies. It is important, however, to pause and consider this historical situation. There are many twentieth-century philosophers who think that philosophy is an autonomous discipline whose history can be ignored; some contemporary philosophers regard philosophy of science as having come into existence only in this century, or maybe in the late nineteenth century.

Keywords

Scientific Theory Empirical Content Universal Generalization Sentential Theory Observation Sentence 
These keywords were added by machine and not by the authors. This process is experimental and the keywords may be updated as the learning algorithm improves.

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Bibliography

  1. Butts, Robert E., “Feyerabend and the Pragmatic Theory of Observation,” Philosophy of Science, XXXIII, 4 (1966).Google Scholar
  2. Butts, Robert E., William Whewell’s Theory of Scientific Method, ed., (Pittsburgh 1968).Google Scholar
  3. Carnap, Rudolf “Testability and Meaning,” Philosophy of Science, 3 (1936) 4 (1937).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Carnap, Rudolf, “Foundations of Logic and Mathematics,” 1,3, International Encyclopedia of Unified Science (Chicago 1939).Google Scholar
  5. Duhem, Pierre, The Aim and Structure of Physical Theory, trans. P.P. Wiener (New York 1962).Google Scholar
  6. Feyerabend, Paul, “Problems of Empiricism I,” Beyond the Edge of Certainty, ed., R. Colodny (Englewood Cliffs, N.J. 1965).Google Scholar
  7. Goodman, Nelson, Fact, Fiction, and Forecast, 2nd ed. (Indianapolis 1965).Google Scholar
  8. Grunbaum, Adolf, Philosophical Problems ofSpace and Time, 2nd ed. (Dordrecht, Holland 1973).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Hempel, Carl, Philosophy of Natural Science, (Englewood Cliffs, N.J. 1966).Google Scholar
  10. Hempel, Carl, Aspects of Scientific Explanation and Other Essays in the Philosophy of Science, (New York & London 1965).Google Scholar
  11. Lewis, C.I., Mind and the World Order, (New York 1956).Google Scholar
  12. Nagel, Ernest, The Structure of Science, (New York & Burlingame 1961).Google Scholar
  13. Popper, Karl, The Logic of Scientific Discovery, (New York 1959).Google Scholar
  14. Quine, W.V., From a Logical Point of View, (Cambridge, Mass. 1953).Google Scholar
  15. Salmon, Wesley, “The Foundations of Scientific Inference,” Mind and Cosmos, ed., R. Colodny (Pittsburgh 1966).Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2000

Authors and Affiliations

  • Graham Solomon
    • 1
  1. 1.Wilfrid Laurier UniversityWaterlooCanada

Personalised recommendations