Skip to main content

Part of the book series: The Western Ontario Series in Philosophy of Science ((WONS,volume 62))

Abstract

What sort of an episode is perception? What are the objects of such episodes? What is the grammatical and logical form of perceptual reports, direct and indirect? Each of these questions has been the subject of recent discussion. In what follows I set out one answer to each of them and explore some of the ways these answers support and complement each other. The answers adopted are: to perceive — and I shall normally only have in mind visual perception — is not to judge or to conceptualize but a sui generis mental mode or activity involving non-conceptual content; perception is of particulars only; the complements of perceptual verbs are, with one exception, non-propositional and indirect perceptual reports are made true by direct perceptual relations between subjects and particulars of various sorts.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. Warnock 1955. Cf. Husserl, Logical Investigations, VI §§ 1–6, 40; Husserl’s account of perception is analysed in Mulligan 1995. The present paper is in many ways a development of Husserl’s account.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Cf. Dretske’s 1969 Seeing and Knowing and chapter 6 of his 1981 Knowledge and the Flow of Information; Jackson 1977, 37ff. & ch. 7; Evans’ account of non-conceptual perceptual information (Evans 1982 §§5.2, 6.3, 7.4); Peacocke 1986, 1989; Ebert 1991.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Rock 1983, 57. Rock is a renegade gestaltist. The minority, gestaltist view in psychology that to see is not to judge goes back to Benussi (cf. Stucchi 1993) and has been ably defended by Gaetano Kanizsa (eg 1985) in his analyses of what he calls perceptual integration.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Dretske 1981, ch. 6. Cf. Peacocke 1989, especially p. 315 on Dretske, Lewis 1971, Turvey 1977.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Brunswik 1934 128, cf. 119f. On this distinction and for a variety of arguments in favour of the view that perception is cognitively impenetrable, see Fodor 1983.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Cf Evans’ (1982, 123, 227) two distinctions (a) between perceptual information and information we obtain by listening to a story (and which is therefore conceptually articulated), and (b) between belief and informational content.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Cf. Evans 1982, 123, Brunswik 1934 128f.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Broad 1925, 153, cf. 208–9

    Google Scholar 

  9. Broad 1925, 153, cf. 208–9.

    Google Scholar 

  10. The internal, phenomenologically immediate connections between perception and action have been analysed as indirect transitions involving kinaesthetic information and body images (Husserl 1973, Evans 1982) and as direct transitions (Koffka 1925, V, §9). Cf. also Prinz 1987.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Cf. Evans 1982, 157: “[t]o say that these things are perceived in a particular manner is not at all to imply that these things are not themselves perceived”; Peacocke 1989, 303.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Cf. Dokic 1998.

    Google Scholar 

  13. The view mentioned above that content is a tokening of mentalese can be combined with the view that there are tokenings of formal concepts other than those mentioned here — non-logical concepts.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Cf. Mulligan, Smith and Simons 1984, Campbell 1990, Simons 1987, ch. 8. The present section develops a claim made at §4 of the first of these.

    Google Scholar 

  15. The view that all universals are formal has much to recommend it.

    Google Scholar 

  16. On the view I favour, an independent particular is composed of tropes that are specifically (or token-) dependent on one another (cf. Husserl’ s third Logical Investigation, Simons 1992). An independent particular, like all particulars, is in time. But its inner internal relations are outside time. This is the grain of truth in the claim that a thing has a history but no temporal parts (cf. Mulligan 1992).

    Google Scholar 

  17. Cf. Mourelatos 1977.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Dretske 1969, 14, 166; cf. Warnock 1955, 209.

    Google Scholar 

  19. In his analysis ofprimary epistemic seeing, Dretske (1969, 141) talks not of simple perception of a relation but of simple seeing of the terms of a relation and the condition that these would not look the way they do unless the relation obtained.

    Google Scholar 

  20. One distant ancestor of the view is Bolzano’s analysis of impersonal sentences such as “It ‘s snowing” as “There is a snow fall” (Wissenschaftslehre § 172).

    Google Scholar 

  21. Armstrong 1978, I, Johansson 1989, ch. 3.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Mulligan, Smith and Simons 1984.

    Google Scholar 

  23. See, for example, Brunswik 1934,1956, von Fieandt 1966.

    Google Scholar 

  24. See Dokic 1998. For an objection to this view, see Mulligan 1996.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Cf Hirsch’s (1982, 106f, 244f) discussion of the views of Quine and the Gestalt psychologists on this matter.

    Google Scholar 

  26. On the related Romance construction, the pseudorelative, cf. Guasti 1992.

    Google Scholar 

  27. The interesting limit case, “a saw John standing”, is perhaps due to the fact that this state is nevertheless an act, something John does.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Cf. Falkenberg 1989.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Perhaps “Sam naked is a sight for sore eyes” is acceptable, perhaps because the main predicate refers to perception. Cf. Parsons 1990, 193.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Cf. Falkenberg 1989.

    Google Scholar 

  31. On perceptual identities see Dretske 1969, 60–61.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Cf. Parsons 1990, ch. 10.

    Google Scholar 

  33. For the view that the truth-maker relation between a truth-bearer and a trope need not involve a detour via quantification over the trope in the form of the truth-bearer, cf. Mulligan, Smith and Simons 1984, 308.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Higginbotham 1983,112f.

    Google Scholar 

  35. Barwise & Perry 1986, 182; Higginbotham 1983,111.

    Google Scholar 

  36. On constructions with “as”, cf Aarts 1992, 111 f.

    Google Scholar 

  37. Even Dretske is of this opinion, Dretske 1990, 133.

    Google Scholar 

  38. This claim involves giving up the strong requirement mentioned in § 1 according to which concepts are employed only in the context of propositions. For an alternative to the strong requirement, see Mulligan 1997, 1997a.

    Google Scholar 

  39. Austin 1962, 101.

    Google Scholar 

  40. On this aspectual difference see Guasti 1992, ch. 6.

    Google Scholar 

  41. Dretske 1969, ch. IV; Jackson 1977, 159–167.

    Google Scholar 

  42. Dretske 1969, 20. “For” might be better.

    Google Scholar 

  43. Cf. Rock 1983, 51.

    Google Scholar 

  44. Goldmeier 1972, 62.

    Google Scholar 

  45. Wittgenstein notes that perceptual reports may describe perception of internal relations (LWPP § 152, § 155, § 156).

    Google Scholar 

  46. Elsewhere (Mulligan 1993, 1998 forthcoming) I have given some reasons for thinking that the relational material tropes introduced here as the objects of much perception, can be reduced to different types of internal relations and that things are structured wholes of monadic tropes.

    Google Scholar 

  47. Cf. Mulligan 1988.

    Google Scholar 

  48. PI II, ix. Wittgenstein, however, concentrates on awareness of internal relations in experiences of change of aspect rather than on perception tout court.

    Google Scholar 

  49. Jackson 1977, ch. 2; Kelley 1986, 234ff.

    Google Scholar 

  50. But see Millikan 1991.

    Google Scholar 

  51. Cf. Mulligan 1998.

    Google Scholar 

  52. Cf. McDowell 1994, 7; Bouveresse 1995,10.

    Google Scholar 

  53. Cf. Horn 1989, §5.2. Horn also notes (323) that factives, such as “see that”, are not Neg raisers. De Sousa (1971) argues that one type ofprobability, Bayesian, attaches to belief, another, Bernouillian, to the leap ofjudgement. On this claim, see Dennett 1985.

    Google Scholar 

  54. Cf. Mulligan 1997a, Mulligan & Smith 1986.

    Google Scholar 

  55. Cf. Mulligan 1998.

    Google Scholar 

  56. Acknowledgments are due to the Swiss FNRS (7OUT-029707), which supported the Geneva project on the philosophy of perception and thanks, for comments and criticisms, to the members of the project, Teresa Guasti, Roberto Casati and Jerome Dokic; to audiences in Gargnano (1990), Paris, Aix and Berne, Canberra, Valencia, Prague, Irvine and elsewhere; to Theo Ebert, Gianfranco Soldati and Brian Garrett.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1999 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Mulligan, K. (1999). Perception, Particulars and Predicates. In: Fisette, D. (eds) Consciousness and Intentionality: Models and Modalities of Attribution. The Western Ontario Series in Philosophy of Science, vol 62. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-9193-5_8

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-9193-5_8

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-481-5300-8

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-015-9193-5

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics