Skip to main content

The Baroque Formulation of Consciousness In The Domain Of Phenomenological Clarification

  • Chapter
  • 139 Accesses

Part of the book series: Contributions to Phenomenology ((CTPH,volume 29))

Abstract

Both the Classical and Baroque formulations of consciousness, as well as their criticism in the eighteenth century, presuppose and take for granted, the fourfold, ungrounded ontic conviction of daily life as positing the “metaphysically real,” the indicational appresentation of which is extrapolated from ordinary, common-sensical experience founded on the ungrounded ontic conviction (in Husserl’s lingo, the general positing of the “natural attitude”). As long as the presupposition is in full force, the result of these formulations entails the distinction between the non-simply connected space of the gap rather than the “simply” connected space of daily life. Their confusion, or the attempt to substitute the former for the latter, lead to death, madness, prison.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. Peter Kivy, Sound and Semblance, pp. 86ff.; the posthumously published essay of Adam Smith is found in Adam Smith, Essays on Philosophical Subjects, edited by W. P. D. Wightman, J.C. Bryce & I.S. Ross, pp. 176–209.

    Google Scholar 

  2. See above, pp. 135f.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Kivy, pp. 94, 95. See above, pp. 35f.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Kivy, pp. 96, 98.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Ibid., p. 100.

    Google Scholar 

  6. See above, pp. 218f. and Kivy, pp. 127, and especially 128ff.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Kivy, ibid.; Kivy develops his view pp. 101ff., and especially in Chapter VII with illustrations from Handel, Bach to Beethoven, Honeger and Varèse.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Ibid., pp. 99, 101.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Ibid.., p. 96.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Edmund Husserl, Erfahrung und Urteil, §§74ff. (English translation by James S. Churchill, Experience and Judgment, pp. 298ff.)

    Google Scholar 

  11. Aron Gurwitsch, The Field of Consciousness, pp. 411 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Above, pp.217f., 227ff.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Gurwitsch, p. 412. See also Kersten, “The Occasion and Novelty of Husserl’s Phenomenology of Essence,” pp. 73ff.

    Google Scholar 

  14. See Gurwitsch, op. cit., pp. 391 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Maurice Natanson, “Existentialism and the Theory of Literature,” in Maurice Natanson, Literature, Philosophy and the Social, p. 112.

    Google Scholar 

  16. A typical example may be found in “On Multiple Realities,” Collected Papers, Volume I, p. 230.

    Google Scholar 

  17. See below, pp. 250f., and Husserl, Ideas, Book One, §§ 9ff.

    Google Scholar 

  18. See Kersten, Phenomenological Method: Theory and Practice, §§90f.

    Google Scholar 

  19. See above, pp. 35f.

    Google Scholar 

  20. See Maurice Natanson, “Man as Actor,” pp. 333, 340 and 341.

    Google Scholar 

  21. See Dorion Cairns, “Perceiving, Remembering, Image-Awareness, Feigning Awareness,” pp. 259ff. for the intentive complexity of image-awareness in contradistinction to feigning-awareness. See above, pp. 35ff., 51ff.

    Google Scholar 

  22. See above, p. 237.

    Google Scholar 

  23. There are still other and non-feigning cases of the awareness of the non-presentive; for example, the awareness of something symbolized by a symbol, the awareness of embarrassment expressed by a blush or of a judgment merely expressed by a sentence. Cf. Cairns, op. cit., p. 261.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Making present of the non-presentive is at least one meaning of the admittedly equivocal term in Husserl, Vergegenwärtigung. Here we can only note that a feigned “world” is not ipso facto a feigned fictive “world”—a distinction as Baroque as that of the idea of the compossibility of Art and Science. Moreoever, it is a distinction that lies at the core of the idea of the “fable of the world.” As a result, the “poetics of wonder” is not ipso facto a “poetics of fiction.” Thus whether Mannerist prose works, such as Cervantes’ Don Quijote, can be regarded as “fiction” in terms of the Baroque formulation of consciousness is an open question which cannot be investigated here. Fantastic verisimiltude appresenting the “real” is not necessarily “fiction.”

    Google Scholar 

  25. See Gurwitsch, op. cit.., p. 393.

    Google Scholar 

  26. See Husserl, Erfahrung und Urteil, §39 (English translation, pp, 167ff.); Gurwitsch, The Field of Consciousness, pp. 389, 411f.; Natanson, “Existentialism and the Theory of Literature,” loc. cit., pp. 111 f.

    Google Scholar 

  27. See Maurice Natanson, “Phenomenology of the Aesthetic Object,” pp. 82ff.; “Phenomenology and Theory of Literature,” pp. 91f.; “Existentialism and Theory of Literature,” p.109. See also Jean Hering, “Concerning Image, Idea, and Dream. Phenomenological Notes,” pp. 188ff.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Above, p.238.

    Google Scholar 

  29. In the terms used here, the actor makes present, presentiates, the non-presentive feelings and conduct of Hamlet.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Jean-Paul Sartre, L’Imaginaire. Psychologie phénoménologique de l’imagination, p. 242. (The translation is mine.)

    Google Scholar 

  31. See e.g. Schutz, op. cit., p. 234.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Ernst Ansermet, Les Fondements de la musique dans la conscience, Chapter One; and pp. 142f. (The translations are mine.)

    Google Scholar 

  33. See above, pp. 222f.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Ansermet, p. 143.

    Google Scholar 

  35. Ibid., pp. 149f. (examples pp. 145ff.).

    Google Scholar 

  36. See above, pp. 209ff.

    Google Scholar 

  37. Ibid., pp. 163f., 165. The project itself is one of expression, dictating to the consciousness of music a “closed” melodic road and a completed “form.” Because of, or perhaps in spite of, the Sartrian framework in which Ansermet casts his examination of the consciousness of music and the imagining or feigning of the musical image, his detailed analyses of a very wide spectrum of examples remains valuable and worth concentrated study.

    Google Scholar 

  38. And these “analogues” or “correlates” in the life-world undergo real historical change, e.g., changes in styles of acting, singing, declamation, significations of words, punctuation, grammar, vocabulary, colors, perspectives, and the like.

    Google Scholar 

  39. Natanson, “Phenomenology and Theory of Literature,” loc. cit., p. 96.

    Google Scholar 

  40. Thus phenomenology is not a Platonism because every object is understood as the correlate of an act or group of acts (in the broadest sense) of consciousness, and this holds as much for material things as “essences,” “eidetic domains,” ideal possibilities.

    Google Scholar 

  41. For the idea of the transcendental phenomenological epoché as used here, see Fred Kersten, Phenomenological Method: Theory and Practice, pp. 25ff.

    Google Scholar 

  42. See Fred Kersten, “The Constancy Hypothesis in the Social Sciences,” pp. 524ff. 532f., 538f, 546ff., 552f.

    Google Scholar 

  43. See Kersten, Phenomenological Method: Theory and Practice, §§6, 7.

    Google Scholar 

  44. Sartre, Nausea, pp. 4, 10.

    Google Scholar 

  45. Husserl, Ideas, Book One, pp. 22f., 242f.

    Google Scholar 

  46. Above, p. 160.

    Google Scholar 

  47. Natanson, Anonymity. A Study in the Philosophy of Alfred Schutz, p. 138.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1997 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Kersten, F. (1997). The Baroque Formulation of Consciousness In The Domain Of Phenomenological Clarification. In: Galileo and the ‘Invention’ of Opera. Contributions to Phenomenology, vol 29. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-8931-4_9

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-8931-4_9

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-481-4847-9

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-015-8931-4

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics