Skip to main content

Structural Rationality and Coherentism

  • Chapter
Economic Rationality and Practical Reason

Part of the book series: Theory and Decision Library ((TDLA,volume 24))

  • 401 Accesses

Abstract

Structural irrationality of individual behaviour patterns can only be rectified by a specific form of self-control. This can be illustrated using an ordinary, simply-structured example: a long-standing smoker asks himself whether he ought to give up smoking. The smoker’s subjective valuations are such that the time integral of his value function increases monotonously the sooner he gives up smoking. The valuation does not only include the smoker’s expected general state of health (a probabilistic estimation), but also the pleasure he undoubtedly enjoys in smoking a cigarette, possibly it also includes the damage the smoke of his cigarettes does to other people, etc. If he still does not give up smoking, his case seems to be a clear instance of ‘akrasia’ or weakness of the will: weighing up all different evaluative aspects, he knows what would be the best thing to do, but he still cannot get himself to do it. This interpretation, however, is not conclusive. It might just as well be the case that the smoker acts consequentially rational, if he does not give up smoking — despite the fact that the time integral over his valuation function increases monotonously the sooner he gives it up. The reason for this is that he — as a consequentialist person — is (under normal circumstances) never confronted with the decision to give up smoking.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. The different possibilities and techniques of individual and collective self-binding — which is only one out of a variety of possibilities of self-control — are shown in many facets by J. Elster. But there is one crucial difference: Elster discusses self-binding under the aspect of the prevention of irrational actions, whereas we are here concerned with the prevention of the structure-breaking effects of consequentially rational actions.

    Google Scholar 

  2. ‘Accept’ must here be understood in the weak sense of ‘to agree that the agent attains his goals’.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Even Hare in his (1963) and (1981) maintains that the rules of universalizability logically necessitate an act-utilitarian ethics.

    Google Scholar 

  4. This corresponds to the so-called ‘normative interpretation’ of decision theory.

    Google Scholar 

  5. See ch. 4.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Cf. v. Wright, (1979), ch. 2.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Consequential reasons are those which according to the consequentialist point of view are the only adequate reasons to justify an action.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Cf. Kant, Grundlegung zur Metaphysik der Sitten, AA 421.

    Google Scholar 

  9. See my (1993b), ch. 9 and 10.

    Google Scholar 

  10. The classical theory claiming that justice and good life coincide — as e. g. presented in Plato’s Gorgias — surely is too optimistic. However, here the problem is articulated while the modern schism of good life and moral duty constitutes an avoidance of the problem.

    Google Scholar 

  11. For details see Tuomela, (1984), ch. 4, and Nida-Rümelin (1986), pp. 96–108.

    Google Scholar 

  12. See the contributions in Elster (1986).

    Google Scholar 

  13. This comprises, under an interpersonal aspect, inter alia the axiological theory of social institutions and under an intrapersonal aspect the theory of good forms of life.

    Google Scholar 

  14. In the course of two and a half millenia much has been thought and written with regard to the relation between self-love and reason, viz. justice which could enrich the contemporary debate on practical rationality. Just to take two examples from many, cf. on the one hand the second letter of Alexander Pope (1733) in which the author starts by saying that man has a natural interest in others’ welfare, and he takes humanity to be connected to a harmonic whole by a ‘chain of love’; on the other hand, Duc de La Rochefoucauld (1665) analyzes even apparently altruistic behaviour as being irrational, egoistic and unfree.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1997 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Nida-Rümelin, J. (1997). Structural Rationality and Coherentism. In: Economic Rationality and Practical Reason. Theory and Decision Library, vol 24. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-8814-0_10

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-8814-0_10

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-481-4828-8

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-015-8814-0

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics