Skip to main content

Part of the book series: Fundamental Theories of Physics ((FTPH,volume 65))

Abstract

We present a brief exposition of the orthodox axiomatic approach to q.m., indicating the relation to the text-book approach. We explain why the usual axioms force a change of logic. We then explain the attempts to derive the Hilbert space and the probability interpretation from a new type of ‘and’ and ‘or’ or a new type of ‘if’ and ‘not’. Included are the Birkhoff-von Neumann, Jauch-Piron, and quantum logic approaches, together with an account of their physical and mathematical obscurities.

Instead of entering the labyrinth of subsequent developments, which seek new algebraic structures while accepting the old physical motivation, we present an exposition of the structured-time interpretation of q.m., which seeks a new physical motivation.

We saw in Chapter VB that, with a tilt in the arrow of time, the solutions of the many-body equations of motion are intrinsically non-unique. In Chapter VIA we had indicated how this non-uniqueness relates to a change in the logic of time. We now explain how the resulting changes in the logic and structure of time lead to a new type of ‘if’ and ‘not’, of the kind required by q.m., while escaping from the criticism which applies to the earlier ‘quantum logic’ approaches.

We briefly indicate the analogy between this logic and the temporal logic required for the formal semantics of parallel-processing languages like OCCAM, and distinguish the structured-time interpretation from the superficially similar many-worlds interpretation and the transactional interpretation of q.m.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes and References

  1. Though we do not enter into this question here, a structured time is also closer to the time of daily experience.

    Google Scholar 

  2. For those who have only vaguely heard of measure theory, the significance of Borel sets is that it always makes sense to speak of the measure of such a set with respect to a regular Borel measure! The significance of a (finite) regular Borel measure is that it corresponds (both ways) to an integral which will (i) integrate continuous functions, and (ii) provide a finite value for the integral of a continuous function which ‘vanishes at infinity’, i.e., is less than the proverbial epsilon outside a compact set. The formal definition of a Borel set in a topological space Xis that it is an element of Bx, the smallest a-algebra which contains all open sets.

    Google Scholar 

  3. P. R. Halmos, Introduction to Hilbert space and the Theory of Spectral Multiplicity, Chelsea, New York, 1951. The whole book is devoted to the proof of this theorem.

    Google Scholar 

  4. From Dirac’s classic treatise on Quantum Mechanics,as cited by J.S. Bell, Speakable and Unspeakable in Quantum Mechanics (Cambridge: University Press, 1987), p 40.

    Google Scholar 

  5. For the difficulties in extending von Neumann’s collapse postulate to observables with continuous spectra, and for a new formulation see M.D. Srinivas, ‘Collapse postulate for observables with continuous spectra’, Commun. Math. Phys., 71, 131–58 (1980).

    Article  Google Scholar 

  6. E. P. Wigner, Phys. Rev., 40, 749 (1932).

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  7. E. P. Wigner, in: Perspectives in Quantum Theory, W. Yourgrau and A. van der Merwe (eds), MIT Press, Cambridge, Mass., 1971.

    Google Scholar 

  8. The other possibility, pursued for instance in stochastic quantization, is to change the axiomatic basis of q.m., so that joint probability distributions do exist even for canonically conjugate variables.

    Google Scholar 

  9. For the measure-theoretic foundations of probability theory, as enunciated by Kolmogorov, see, for instance, P. Halmos, Measure Theory, D. Van Nostrand, New York, 1950. To change from sets to sentences, see, e.g., J. R. Lucas, The Foundations of Probability, Clarendon, Oxford, 1957.

    Google Scholar 

  10. The logico-algebraic approach was initiated by G. Birkhoff and J. von Neumann, Ann. Math., 37, 823 (1936). For further developments of this theory, see V.S. Varadarajan, Geometry of Quantum Theory, Vol. 1, Van Nostrand, Princeton, N.J., 1968, and C. A. Hooker (ed) The Logico AlgebraicApproach to Quantum Mechanics, D. Reidel, Dordrecht, 1975.

    Google Scholar 

  11. A ‘subspace’ will always mean a closed linear manifold.

    Google Scholar 

  12. One has to be a little careful in applying the analogy to implication. The sentential connective should not be confused with the relation of implication. Thus, it makes sense to speak of (B’’A),but not of a_ (b _a).

    Google Scholar 

  13. See G. Kalmbach, Hilbert Lattices,World Scientific, Singapore, 1987, for a counter-example, which however, does not apply to probability measures.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Those interested in probing further may like to be discouraged by the text of S. Lang, Algebra, Addison-Wesley, Reading, Mass., 1965.

    Google Scholar 

  15. C. K. Raju, ‘Quantum mechanics and the microphysical structure of time’ [1990]. In: R. Nair (ed) In Search of Quantum Reality (to appear).

    Google Scholar 

  16. This is true directly for charged particles, and indirectly, at least, for all particles which interact in any way with charged particles.

    Google Scholar 

  17. The whole debate over ‘hidden variables’ is related to the metaphysical assumption (of linear time) that ‘reality is unambiguous’. This assumption breaks down with branching time.

    Google Scholar 

  18. The terminology derives from temporal logic.

    Google Scholar 

  19. See, e.g., K.R. Apt (ed), Logics and Models of Concurrent Systems,Springer, Berlin, 1984, NATO ASI Series in Computers and Systems Science, Vol. 13. The moral of the story is that one should link non-locality to CSP rather than ESP!

    Google Scholar 

  20. The usual definition of a random variable as a measurable function assumes the possibility of such an in-principle specification.

    Google Scholar 

  21. N. Rescher and A. Urquhart, Temporal Logic ( Wien: Springer, 1971 ).

    Book  MATH  Google Scholar 

  22. This does not lead to any paradoxes, as discussed in detail in Chapter VB. In terms of the analogy to the formally similar but more pragmatic CSP, the ALT construct of OCCAM is non-deterministic, and the contingent ‘present’ is what accounts for the current practical difficulty in constructing a debugger for parallel processors. Incidentally, in India, this difficulty has been currently resolved by abandoning CSP and adopting a queuing model in the PARAS system software developed by C-DAC for use with parallel FORTRAN, and C, which have some constructs resembling the PAR and ALT of OCCAM. The empirical significance of a contingent past is discussed later on.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Traditionally, a proposition is what a sentence expresses or means. Formally, ‘meaning’ may be deemed to have been assigned to a sentencep by specifying the set of ‘worlds’, Ip I, in which the sentence is true, so that one knows when the sentence is true and when it is false. Since we shall be using different notions of ‘world’, we should have, strictly, distinguished between statements, truth-functional propositions and quasi truth-functional propositions. We shall, however, not retain this difference explicitly, in the hope that the type of entity being considered would be clear from the context.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Bas C. Van Fraassen, in: Hooker (ed) Contemporary Research in Foundations and Philosophy of Quantum Theory, D. Reidel, Dordrecht, 1973, p 84.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Strictly speaking, a state should be identified with a convex combination of the probability measures induced by each q.t.f. world in the collection. Thus, to each q.t.f. world w in a state, one must also assign a number t(w),0t(w)1, such that E t(w) = 1, the sum being taken over all q.t.f. worlds in the state.

    Google Scholar 

  26. The selection function is, in fact, a projection: fp o fp = fp, and could, under the circumstance (25), quite literally be identified with a projection operator in Hilbert space.

    Google Scholar 

  27. W. L. Harper, R. Stalnaker, and G. Pearce (eds), Ifs, D. Reidel, Dordrecht, 1981.

    Google Scholar 

  28. See Harper et al, Ref. 27.

    Google Scholar 

  29. I will use statements and propositions interchangeably; see note 23.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Ref. 15, Theorems 1, and 2.

    Google Scholar 

  31. Ref. 15, Theorem 5, equivalence of (i) and (v).

    Google Scholar 

  32. Ref. 15.

    Google Scholar 

  33. J.C.T. Pool, (reproduced in Hooker, Ref. 24 above). In the next paper in Hooker (ed), Pool also considers the possible significance of semi-modularity.

    Google Scholar 

  34. J. G. Cramers, Rev. Mod. Phys., 58, 647 (1986).

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  35. See van Fraassen, Ref. 24.

    Google Scholar 

  36. As a specific example, consider van Fraassen’s assumption (2), in Ref. 24, corresponding to Pool’s Axiom 1.3, in Ref. 33. This says that Op Oq implies Op 0 q. That is, if the necessity ofp implies the necessity of q,then the possibility of p implies the possibility of q. I do not know of any traditional modal logic in which this is true.

    Google Scholar 

  37. C. K. Raju, Int. J. Theor. Phys., 20, 681 (1980).

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1994 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Raju, C.K. (1994). Quantum-Mechanical Time. In: Time: Towards a Consistent Theory. Fundamental Theories of Physics, vol 65. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-8376-3_10

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-8376-3_10

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-481-4462-4

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-015-8376-3

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics