Skip to main content

The Existence of Augustinian ‘Metaphysics’

  • Chapter
St. Augustine and being
  • 97 Accesses

Abstract

One might think that the title above raises an idle question. And indeed in a sense it does. Could a theologian get on with his business at all without reasoning in universal terms about what universally is? Lacking general notions on the nature of being-ingeneral, could he even begin to work out a theory of its Principle ? By what means could he then build a theology?

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 69.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 89.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. “Porro si sapientia Deus est, per quern facta sunt omnia, sicut divina auctoritas veritasque monstravit (Sap. VII, 24-27); et Hebr. I, 2, 3), verus philosophus est amator Dei. (The City of God, VIII, 1 (PL 41, 224-225); italics added. “Obsecro te, non sit honestior philosophia Gentium quam nostra Christiana, quae una est vera philosophia, quandoquidem Studium vel amor sapientiae significatur hoc nomine.” (Against Julian the Pelagian, IV, 14.72 (PL 44, 774); italics added.

    Google Scholar 

  2. See preceding note.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Sermon XLIII, 7.9 (PL 38,253). Cf. Epistle CXX, I, 3 (PL 33,453); On St. John’s Gospel, XXXVI, 7 (PL 35, 1667).

    Google Scholar 

  4. “Haec est sapientiae et scientiae recta distinctio, ut ad sapientian pertineat aeternarum rerum cognitio intellectualis: ad scientiam vero temporalium reum cognitio rationalis.” The Trinity, XII, 15.25 (P L 42, 1012).

    Google Scholar 

  5. Cf. Soliloquies I, 6.13 (PL 32, 876); On St. John’s Gospel, XXXV, 8.3 (PL 35, 1658). The texts on this “illumination” are very numerous. See A. Martin, S. Augustini Philosophia, II, ch. 32 (ed. Fabre) for a collection of many of the principal statements concerning this celebrated and much controverted topic in Augustine; and one especially recommends the excellent gathering of texts by L. W. Keeler, S.J., Sancti Augustini doctrina de cognitione, Romae, 1934. It would be irrelevant for us to enter here into the problems and controversies involved.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Confessions, X 23.33 (PL 32, 793); The Trinity, X, 3.5 (PL 42, 975); On the Blessed Life, II, II (PL 32, 965); 11, 14 (PL 32, 966); III, 18 (PL 32, 968), etc.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Against Julian the Pelagian, IV, 14.72 (PL 44, 774). Cf. The City of God, VIII, 9 (PL 41, 233); On the Christian Way of Life, I, 21.38 (PL 32, 1327).

    Google Scholar 

  8. E.g., Enneads, V, 1, 7.

    Google Scholar 

  9. E.g., Republic, VI, 508 E-509 B.

    Google Scholar 

  10. E.g., See Victorinus, On the Generation of the Divine Word (Liber de generatione Verbi divini, ch. 4-5), (PL 8, 1022; 13, 1027); The Book on Causes (Liber de Causis), e.g., Par 2, 5, 21 (ed. Bardenhewer, Freiburg im Breisgau, 1882, pp. 165, 168, 183; Pseudo-Dionysius, On the Divine Names (De divinis nominibus), IV, 3.

    Google Scholar 

  11. While this reading, based on the Septuagint (a Greek version of the O. T. made between 280 and 130 B. C), is not a perfectly literal rendering of the Hebrew original, that problem is here metaphysically irrelevant; for Augustine’s understanding of its ontological import agrees precisely with the Christian idea of God as the single Supreme Being and is therefore incompatible with any opposing metaphysical interpretation. It is pertinent to note that Augustine ascribes pre-eminent authority to the Septuagint because he firmly believed that God had provided that version for the instruction of the Gentiles even as He had provided the Hebrew text for the instruction of the Hebrews. That is why (according to Augustine) the Holy Spirit had inspired the Septuagint translators to deviate at times from the Hebrew text: only by doing so could they express the truth in the manner in which God willed it to be expressed to the Gentiles. See On Christian Doctrine, II, 15.22 (PL 34, 46); The City of God, XVIII, 43 (PL 41, 604). See below, Ch. X, p. 74 n. 3.

    Google Scholar 

  12. E.g., in Sermon VI, 3.4 (PL 38, 61); VII, 7 (PL 38, 66); The City of God, XII, 2 (PL 41, 350); The Trinity, V, 2.3 (PL 42, 912).

    Google Scholar 

  13. Etienne Gilson, Being and Some Philosophers, 2nd edition, Toronto, 1952, p. 31.

    Google Scholar 

  14. “Ipsum esse se vocari respondit; et tamquam hoc esset ei nomen: Hoc dices eis, inquit, Qui est, misit me” (Exodus 3: 14). Commentary on Psalm CXXXIV, 4 (PL 37, 1741).

    Google Scholar 

  15. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Non dixit, Dominus Deus ille “omnipotens, “misericors,” “Justus,” quae si diceret, utique vera diceret. Sublatis de medio omnibus quibus appellari posset et dici Deus, “ipsum esse” se vocari respondit; et tamquam hoc esset ei nomen: “Hoc dices eis, inquit, Qui est, misit me.”Ibid. See above, note 3.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Note that Augustine says “essentia.” See below, chapter IX for the meaning of this important term in Augustine.

    Google Scholar 

  18. The City of God, XII, 2 (PL 41, 350).

    Google Scholar 

  19. On the True Religion, XVIII, 35 (PL 34, 137).

    Google Scholar 

  20. Ibid. See Augustine’s lengthy development of the doctrine of creatio ex nihilo in his treatise Against Felix the Manichean, II, 18 (PL 42, 547-48). Cf. C. O’Toole, The Philosophy of Creation in the writings of St. Augustine, Washington, 1944.

    Google Scholar 

  21. On the True Religion, XVIII, 36 (PL 34, 137).

    Google Scholar 

  22. Confessions, XII, 6.6 (PL 32, 827).

    Google Scholar 

  23. Ibid., also XII, 8.8 (PL 32, 829).

    Google Scholar 

  24. A Literal Commentary on “Genesis,” I, 15, 29 (PL 34, 257).

    Google Scholar 

  25. Op. cit., PL 8, 1022; PL 13, 1027.

    Google Scholar 

  26. Enneads, V, 1.7.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Enneads, V, 1.10.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Enneads, V. 3.13. Italics added.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Parmenides, 141 E; Republic, VI, 509 B.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Plotinus, Enneads, V, 4.1.

    Google Scholar 

  31. Cf. Enneads, V, 5.6.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Enneads, V, 3.13.

    Google Scholar 

  33. See J. Anderson, The Bond of Beins, St. Louis: Herder, 1949, esp. pp. 67-68.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Cf. Op. cit., ch. III.

    Google Scholar 

  35. E.g., see L. Grandgeorge, Saint Augustin et le neéo-platonisme, Paris, Leroux, 1896; G. M. Manser, “Augustinus Philosophie in ihrem Verhàltnis und ihrer Abhàngigkeit von Plotin,” Divus Thomas, vol. X, 1932.

    Google Scholar 

  36. Answer to the Skeptics, III, 20.43 (PL 32, 957).

    Google Scholar 

  37. Summa Theologiae, I, q. 84, a. 5.

    Google Scholar 

  38. The City of God, VIII, I (PL 41, 224).

    Google Scholar 

  39. E.g., see On the True Religion, V, 8 (PL 43, 129); The City of God, VIII, 8 (PL 41, 232-33); VIII, 4 (PL 41, 227-29); The Christian Way of Life, 1,16.26 (PL 32, 1322); I, 8.13 (PL 32, 1316); I, 14.24 (PL 32, 1321).

    Google Scholar 

  40. Cf. St. Thomas Aquinas, Summa Theologiae, I, q. 1, a. 2 and a. 6.

    Google Scholar 

  41. Cf. J. Maritain, Les degreés du savoir, Paris: Desclée de Brouwer, 4th ed., 1946, ch. VII, 8; authorized English version: Distinguish to Unite or The Degrees of Knowledge, translated under the supervision of G.B. Phelan, New York: Scribners, 1959.

    Google Scholar 

  42. Maritain, op. cit., p. 595; English version, p. 300.

    Google Scholar 

  43. E.g., see The City of God, VIII, 8 (PL 41, 232-33).

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1965 Martinus Nijhoff, The Hague, Netherlands

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Anderson, J.F. (1965). The Existence of Augustinian ‘Metaphysics’. In: St. Augustine and being. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-011-9447-1_1

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-011-9447-1_1

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-94-011-8655-1

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-011-9447-1

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics