Skip to main content

Infinite Mind

  • Chapter
  • 86 Accesses

Abstract

In the time immediately following the appearance of Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason the old metaphysical systems were being undermined by the “all-crushing” (“der alleszermaltnende”) Kant and the new metaphysics of Fichte and the Philosophy of Identity had not yet come into their own. In this transitional period the attention of the philosophical world in Germany was centered in the interpretation of Kantian philosophy, and especially in the understanding of the concept of the thing-in-itself. With reference to the latter Jacobi and Maimon went further than their contemporaries. Reinhold and Beck, whose contributions consisted in interpreting and explaining Kant,1 made the Kantian philosophy accessible to wider circles. Reinhold’s interpretation of Kant betrays the difficulties and apparent contradictions of critical philosophy. Jacobi and Maimon, however, grasp the full implications of the new philosophy and with respect to the problem of the thing-in-itself draw the conclusions that necessarily follow from the principles of critical philospohy. Jacobi questions the possibility of the very concept of the thing-in-itself in a system of thought that declares the object of cognition to be confined to the realm of phenomena. His analysis, however, led him away from critical philosophy to romanticism and to the adoption of a philosophical viewpoint in opposition to Kant. Maimon, on the other hand, declares that the concept of the thing-in-itself belongs to the realm of ideas in the Kantian sense, which can be approached endlessly but never fully attained. Maimon thus gives meaning and significance to the concept of the thing-in-itself in the authentic spirit of the Kantian philosophy.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. See Karl L. Reinhold, Briefe über die Kantische Philosophie (1790), and Siegmund Beck, Einzig möglicher Standpunkt aus welchem die kritische Philosophie beurteilt werden muss (1796).

    Google Scholar 

  2. Tr., p. 419; Kat. d. Arist., p. 143; Krit. Unt., pp. 155-158.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Cf. Wilhelm Dilthey, Gesammelte Schriften, IV, 50, where he writes of Fichte that he prepared the way for the development of the concept of the objective spirit and of the form of pantheism that was evolved through metaphysical dialectics, and then adds: “If the methods of critical analysis, as developed by Lambert, Kant and Maimon, had been further pursued… the course of the development of philosophy would have been entirely different.”

    Google Scholar 

  4. See “Über die Progressen der Philosophie,” in Str., p. 58.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Cf. Tr., pp. 171, 443.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Cf. TV., pp. 48 f.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Ibid., p. 50.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Ibid., p. 51.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Ibid., p. 54.

    Google Scholar 

  10. By logical possibility is meant the deduction of reality from a priori principles, and not merely freedom from contradiction. Cf. below, Chap. VIII.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Tr. pp. 56 f.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Ibid., p. 57; cf. below, Chap. IX.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Tr., pp. 58 f.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Ibid., p. 62.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Ibid., pp. 62 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Ibid., pp. 64 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Lebensgeschichte, II, p. 253.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Com. on the Guide, qiv’at Hammoreh (Hebrew), p. 9b, also 12a.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Friedrich Kuntze, Die Philosophie Salomon Maimons, pp. 276, 307, and 341.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Cf. Str., p. 26: “… nicht eine zufällige äussere, sondern eine wesentliche innere Harmonie, die nicht bloss von einer Willkür sondern von einem Willen, der in der Natur der Objekte selbst seinen Grund hat, abhängt.”

    Google Scholar 

  21. Ibid., p. 36: “Nach der Art wie ich mir Leibnizens System denke, …bezieht sich der unendliche Verstand Gottes auf alle mögliche Dinge… die in Ansehung seiner zugleich wirklich sind. Die in Ansehung unserer wirklichen Welt ist nichts anderes als der Inbegriff aller möglichen Dinge von uns auf eine eingeschränkte A rt vorgestellt. Von diesem Inbegriff alles möglichen wird nur so viel als wirklich von uns vorgestellt, wie viel die Materie (unsere eigene Einschränkung) zulässt…”

    Google Scholar 

  22. G. W. von Leibniz, Philosophische Schriften (Gerhard edition), VII, a.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Ibid., p. 200. The translation is by Bertrand Russell. Cf. Bertrand Russell, The Philosophy of Leibniz (Cambridge, 1900), p. 61.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Russell, op. cit., p. 62. However, cf. A. O. Lovejoy, The Great Chain of Being. A Study of the History of an Idea (Cambridge, Mass., 1936), p. 354, n. 68.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Cf. L. Couturat, Opuscules et fragments inédits de Leibniz (Paris, 1903). See especially p. 18.

    Google Scholar 

  26. Friedrich Paulsen is thus incorrect in interpreting the Kantian concept of an infinite reason in the following manner: “The reality, as it is in itself, is thought by us as having its roots in an intellectus archetypus, in an absolute and intuitive reason, which conceives as a system of existing ideas” (cf. Friedrich Paulsen, “Kants Idealismus,” in Kritizismus, eine Sammlung von Beiträgen aus der Welt des Neu-Kantianismus, ed. Friedrich Myrho [Berlin, 1926], p. 3). This interpretation of Paulsen is bound up with his dogmatic conception of the Kantian things-in-themselves as realities per se to which our thinking is inexorably and necessarily driven. Paulsen writes: “We determine by necessary thinking the realm of ‘things-in-themselves’ i.e., the intelligible world… we determine them as a system of ideas which have their root and unity in an absolute spirit” (ibid.). Such a conception of Kant’s position would involve us in contradictions and difficulties and is incompatible with the very spirit of critical philosophy, which confines the realm of cognition to the sphere of phenomena. Things-in-themselves must therefore be understood in a critical sense as limiting concepts, and correspondingly, the idea of an infinite reason cannot be arrived at through the medium of things-in-themselves as real entities. According to Kant, the infinite reason is rather an idea conceived for the purpose of stressing the limitations of the human mind arising from its inherent dualism of sensibility and understanding.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Philos. Wört., p. 169.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Guide, III, 20.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Ibid., I, 68.

    Google Scholar 

  30. See above, p. 75.

    Google Scholar 

  31. Magazin zur Erfahrungsseelenkunde, Vol. X, 2tes Stück, p. 55.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Ibid., p. 61.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Ibid., p. 62.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Cf. below, Chap. VIII, “Principle of Determinability.”

    Google Scholar 

  35. See TV., p. 87, n.

    Google Scholar 

  36. See below, Chap. VI.

    Google Scholar 

  37. Com. to the Guide, Chap. 1.

    Google Scholar 

  38. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  39. See Tr., p. 366.

    Google Scholar 

  40. Ibid., p. 365.

    Google Scholar 

  41. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  42. This seems to be ontological thinking in the same way that it is implied in some trends of modern phenomenology, especially as developed into ontological phenomenology by Max Scheler and Nicolai Hartmann. They all make the transition from the intentional character of our thought, i.e., that it is directed towards an object, to the ontological reality of the object. Maimon seems to have been aware of this problem. In his Krit. Unt., p. 161, Maimon tries to show that we have a concept of the absolute totality of the conditions implying the idea of an unconditional reality. This concept must have its ground in the function of our cognitive capacity. And since our sensibility and understanding are confined to the empirical realm and cannot be the basis for the unconditioned, this concept must have its ground in the capacity of reason (Vernunft). Having in mind the objection that may be raised, that it is not legitimate to make a transition from a mere form of reason to an object, Maimon writes: “Nevertheless, the concept cannot be completely empty; even though it is not of a constitutive nature and cannot determine an object, it has a regulative use, in that it directs our understanding to search constantly for the totality of the conditions and to proceed from condition to condition, and so on, ad infinitum.”

    Google Scholar 

  43. Critique of Pure Reason, Smith translation, p. 182.

    Google Scholar 

  44. Ibid., p. 187.

    Google Scholar 

  45. Cf. below, Chap. X, p. 192 f.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1964 Martinus Nijhoff, The Hague. Netherlands

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Atlas, S. (1964). Infinite Mind. In: From Critical to Speculative Idealism. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-011-9106-7_5

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-011-9106-7_5

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-94-011-8400-7

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-011-9106-7

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics