Skip to main content

The Esthetic Letters

  • Chapter
Freedom and Dignity
  • 57 Accesses

Abstract

For a correct assessment of Über die ästhetische Erziehung des Menschen in einer Reihe von Briefen, it is necessary to abandon the modern conception of “esthetic.” The idea of beauty as a joy-for-ever, and of art for art’s sake has had a detrimental effect on the proper evaluation of Schiller’s esthetic theories. Esthetic, for Schiller, meant reconciliation, unity. It presented, as we shall see, a synthesis suspending the polarity of the sensate and the intelligent forces in man’s mind.

Der spielende Mensch hält der Freiheit stand; er sichert sie, er verleiht ihr Dauer. Gustav Bally

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. Walter Grossmann, op. cit., p. 156.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Jonas III, p. 248.

    Google Scholar 

  3. October 20,’ 94. Jonas IV, p. 40.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Letter to Schiller of October 26, 94.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Tomaschek, p. 277.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Werke (HA), XI, 2.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Ibid., XI, 3.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Letter of June 27,’ 95, replying to Schiller’s rejection of a contribution to the Horen.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Werke (HA) XI, 3.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Ibid., 5.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Ibid., 11.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Ibid., 13.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Ibid., 13.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Ibid., 14.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Ibid., 14.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Buchwald, p. 274.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Werke (HA) XI, 15.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Schiller’s Werke (SA) Vol. XII, p. 362.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Op. cit., p. 105. In spite of this influence from Herder, Herder himself was one of the few among Schiller’s friends who did not much enjoy the Esthetic Letters. He dismissed them as “Kantian sins.”

    Google Scholar 

  20. Werke (HA), XI, 16.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Ibid., 17.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Ibid., 21-23.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Ibid., 23.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Ibid., 24.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Ibid., 28. Cf. Schiller’s letter to the Duke of Augustenburg of July 13, 1793: “Every thorough improvement of the state must start with the purifying of the character, this however must be guided by the beautiful and noble.” Jonas III, p. 339.

    Google Scholar 

  26. Ibid., 28.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Ibid., 29.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Arnold Littmann for instance, op. cit., p. 94, who sees Goethe’s influence in Schiller’s attention to “the ideal of esthetic civilization, the beautiful soul, the living form.”

    Google Scholar 

  29. Jonas IV, p. 40.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Werke (HA) XI, 29.

    Google Scholar 

  31. Ibid., 32.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Ibid., 40.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Ibid., 42.

    Google Scholar 

  34. For form urge Schiller uses the term Formtrieb, for material urge sinnlicher Trieb. Stofftrieb, or Sachtrieb.

    Google Scholar 

  35. German: aufheben, a term to play an important role in Hegel’s dialectics. It is practically untranslatable, since it combines the connotations to supersede, preserve and elevate. Cf. Carl J. Friedrich’s Introduction to The philosophy of Hegel, New York, 1953, p. xxix.

    Google Scholar 

  36. Werke (HA) XI, 50.

    Google Scholar 

  37. Ibid., 51.

    Google Scholar 

  38. Ibid., 53.

    Google Scholar 

  39. Schiller refers to the Philosophical Inquiry into the Origin of our Ideas on the Sublime and Beautiful (1756), which treats the subject entirely empirically and physically, causing A. W. Schlegel to remark that under those circumstances beauty could be bought in a drug store. See Arthur Jung, op. cit., p. 237.

    Google Scholar 

  40. In a footnote Schiller mentions in this connection A.R. Mengs, an important painter of the time, who wrote essays on the principles of his own work. (Collected and published in 1786.)

    Google Scholar 

  41. Werke (HA), XI, 57.

    Google Scholar 

  42. The pre-socratic philosophers were already occupied with the problem of polarity. The pythagoraic thinker Philolaos (4th cent. B.C.) says “Harmony is the comprehensive unity of a manifold composite, and concord in discord.”

    Google Scholar 

  43. Werke (HA), XI, 59.

    Google Scholar 

  44. Wiese, op. cit., p. 496.

    Google Scholar 

  45. Letter to Fichte, Aug. 3rd, ′95. Jonas IV, p. 221.

    Google Scholar 

  46. Ibid., IV, p. 274.

    Google Scholar 

  47. Werke, (HA) XI, 73.

    Google Scholar 

  48. Ibid., 74.

    Google Scholar 

  49. Ibid., 75. This is confirmed in a letter to Charlotte von Schimmelmann, November 4th, 1795, in which Schiller points out that “all tracts of the human mind end up in poetry.” “The best philosophy ends in a poetic idea, similarly the best morality, the best politics. The poetic spirit shows to all three the ideal, to approximate to which is the highest perfection.” Jonas IV, p. 315.

    Google Scholar 

  50. Werke (HA) XI, 78.

    Google Scholar 

  51. Ibid., 84.

    Google Scholar 

  52. Wiese, p. 499.

    Google Scholar 

  53. Werke (HA) VII, 101.

    Google Scholar 

  54. Ibid., VII, 102.

    Google Scholar 

  55. Ibid., XI, 89.

    Google Scholar 

  56. Ibid., 89.

    Google Scholar 

  57. Letter to the Duke of Augustenburg, Nov. 11,’ 93, Jonas III, p. 386.

    Google Scholar 

  58. Werke, (HA), XI, 92.

    Google Scholar 

  59. Ibid., XI, 98.

    Google Scholar 

  60. Ibid., XI, 99.

    Google Scholar 

  61. Ibid., XI, 99.

    Google Scholar 

  62. Ibid., XI, 99.

    Google Scholar 

  63. Ibid., XI, 102. Schiller hastens to add the warning that he is obviously only talking about esthetic semblance as distinct from reality, and not about the logical one which does not improve reality. The first is play, the latter deceit.

    Google Scholar 

  64. Ibid., XI, 105.

    Google Scholar 

  65. Ibid., XI, 113.

    Google Scholar 

  66. Ibid., 113.

    Google Scholar 

  67. Jonas III, 305.

    Google Scholar 

  68. Ibid., 460. Dated June 14, 1794.

    Google Scholar 

  69. August 3, 1795. Ibid., IV, 218.

    Google Scholar 

  70. Werke (HA) XIII. 279.

    Google Scholar 

  71. Letter to Körner, October 13, 1789. Jonas II, p. 343.

    Google Scholar 

  72. Ibid., IV, p. 110.

    Google Scholar 

  73. May 5, 1795. Jonas IV, 169.

    Google Scholar 

  74. Review of Carlyle’s “Life of Schiller” in The Christian Examiner, July 1834, XVI, 365-392.

    Google Scholar 

  75. Hajo Holborn, “Der deutsche Idealismus in sozialgeschichtlicher Beleuchtung,” Historische Zeitschrift, 1952, 174, p. 366.

    Google Scholar 

  76. Psychological Types, p. 160.

    Google Scholar 

  77. Immanuel Kant, Sämtliche Werke (Hartenstein ed.) Leipzig, 1867, Band V, II, p. 230.

    Google Scholar 

  78. Ibid., p. 364.

    Google Scholar 

  79. Ibid., p. 331.

    Google Scholar 

  80. Ibid., p. 342.

    Google Scholar 

  81. Werke (HA), XI, 109. This contradicts Ernst Cassirer’s assertion that there is no point of contact between Schiller and modern biological theories of play. Essay on Man. New York, 1944, p. 210.

    Google Scholar 

  82. Ibid., 109.

    Google Scholar 

  83. Ibid., 110.

    Google Scholar 

  84. It lies outside our province to deal, in detail, with the great number of physiological, biological and psychological theories of play. A short summary of the most influential explanations of the phenomenon play, may suffice. Schiller’s surplus theory was shared by Jean Paul and by the German psychologist Beneke (Empirical Psychology as the Basis of Knowledge, 1820). It was Herbert Spencer, however, who made it generally known in his Principles of Psychology (1855), where he stresses the “overflow of energy.” Another theory is based on imitation, presented for instance in Wundt’s Vorlesungen über die Menschen-und Tierseele (Leipzig, 1862). Karl Groos (Die Spiele der Tiere, and Die Spiele des Menschen, Jena, 1899) became famous for his conception of play as preparatory training, and the German school of Lazarus (Ueber die Reize des Spiels, Berlin 1883) etc., produced the theory of play as relaxation. Then there is the purge-theory, by which an Aristotelian principle of tragedy is applied to play by Harvey A. Carr (The Survival Values of Play, Colorado, 1902) and the completion theory of Konrad Lange (Das Wesen der Kunst, Berlin, 2nd ed. 1907). Most of these theories stress only one function of play and H. Zondervan in Het spel by dieren, kinderen en volwassen menschen, Amsterdam, 1928, p. 58, denies that any of them could represent alone the phenomenon of play as such.

    Google Scholar 

  85. J. Huizinga, Homo ludens, proeve eener bepaling van het spel-element der cultuur, Haarlem, 1938, p. 4.

    Google Scholar 

  86. Ibid., p. 4.

    Google Scholar 

  87. Schelling, op cit. I, p. 707.

    Google Scholar 

  88. In a recent dissertation, Jeanne Hersch combines Fichte’s system with Jasper’s Existentialism in her concept of play: “Man plays his entire existence in the relationship between two opposed and inseparable terms: I and non-I.” (L’Etre et la Forme, Genève, 1946, p. 21).

    Google Scholar 

  89. Werke (HA) IX, 83.

    Google Scholar 

  90. Ibid., IX, 238. In modern Existentialism this dualism is heightened in the paradox of life itself. Gustav Bally in Vom Ursprung und von den Grenzen der Freiheit, Basel, 1945, introduces the element of play in this paradox: “In the background of human life is death and abyss. Only on this ground emerges the world, discovered in elucidating play.” (p. 73) The word elucidating (erhellend) is from Jasper’s terminology, who himself wrote in this connection: “Life as appearance of existence is the way from potentiality to absolute reality; for life the complexity, as potentiality, is play.” (Philosophie, Berlin, 1932, Band II, IX, 2).

    Google Scholar 

  91. Ibid., XI, 49.

    Google Scholar 

  92. Ibid., 49.

    Google Scholar 

  93. Ibid., 50.

    Google Scholar 

  94. It seems relevant here to mention Jung who contributed an important study of Schiller as a “thinking introvert,” and who was a life-long student of symbolic polarity. “The symbol is neither abstract nor concrete, neither rational nor irrational, neither real nor unreal. It is always both.” Coll. Works, V, 12, 270.

    Google Scholar 

  95. With Jung the polarity of formative conscious (Sinn) and the collective unconscious (Bild). The etymology of the Greek word leads, of course, to the throwing together of two or more different entities.

    Google Scholar 

  96. Kant, op. cit., V, II, 59.

    Google Scholar 

  97. Werke (HA), XI, 53.

    Google Scholar 

  98. Ibid., 54.

    Google Scholar 

  99. Ibid., 56.

    Google Scholar 

  100. Ibid., 56.

    Google Scholar 

  101. Huizinga, op. cit., 105.

    Google Scholar 

  102. Pindari carmina, Londini, 1821, 44.

    Google Scholar 

  103. See Part I, 3.

    Google Scholar 

  104. Friedrich Schlegel, 1794–1802, Jakob Minor, ed., II, 296.

    Google Scholar 

  105. Ibid., 198. Kierkegaard, in his doctoral dissertation (German translation Über den Begriff der Ironie, by H. H. Schaeder, München 1939), is opposed to Romantic irony and points instead to irony as a “controlled moment” (p. 271) which would have attracted Schiller, for it means the fundamental condition of play-polarity.

    Google Scholar 

  106. Werke (HA), XI, 57.

    Google Scholar 

  107. Ibid., 57.

    Google Scholar 

  108. Ibid., 57.

    Google Scholar 

  109. Werke (HA) XI, p. 17.

    Google Scholar 

  110. Neumann, op. cit., p. 271.

    Google Scholar 

  111. Ibid., p. 272.

    Google Scholar 

  112. Der entfremdete Mensch, Basel, 1953, p. 28.

    Google Scholar 

  113. Werke (HA) XI, 114.

    Google Scholar 

  114. Ibid., XI, 38.

    Google Scholar 

  115. Ibid., XI, 73.

    Google Scholar 

  116. Ibid., XI, 74.

    Google Scholar 

  117. Rep. IV, 433.

    Google Scholar 

  118. Herbert Read, Existentialism, Marxism and Anarchism, London 1949, p. 14.

    Google Scholar 

  119. For an extensive etymological development see Huizinga, op. cit. p. 40-60.

    Google Scholar 

  120. Werke (HA) XI, 114.

    Google Scholar 

  121. Ibid., 114.

    Google Scholar 

  122. Ibid., 114.

    Google Scholar 

  123. Urtheilskraft, p. 207.

    Google Scholar 

  124. Werke (HA) XI, 114.

    Google Scholar 

  125. Ibid., 115.

    Google Scholar 

  126. Werke (HA), XI, 116.

    Google Scholar 

  127. Ibid., 116.

    Google Scholar 

  128. Hugo Grotius, De iure belli ac pacis, Amsterdami, Iohannem Blaeu, 1646, III, 27, 1.

    Google Scholar 

  129. Droz, op. cit., p. 311.

    Google Scholar 

  130. Wieland, Gesammelte Schriften, Berlin, 1931, IX, P. 132.

    Google Scholar 

  131. Gooch, C.P. Studies in German History, London, 1948, p. 169. Cf. also Möser’s appraisal of Goethe’s influence on the Duke who, although originally having the tastes of a country squire in love with hunting and shooting, grew into an enlightened protector of the arts. Bruford, W.H. Germany in the Eighteenth Century, Cambridge, 1952, p. 31.

    Google Scholar 

  132. Werke (HA) XIX, 3.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1965 Martinus Nijhoff, The Hague, Netherlands

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Regin, D. (1965). The Esthetic Letters. In: Freedom and Dignity. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-011-9097-8_10

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-011-9097-8_10

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-94-011-8395-6

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-011-9097-8

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics