Skip to main content

Part of the book series: Fundamental Theories of Physics ((FTPH,volume 102))

Abstract

The division of 17th century natural philosophy into natural science on the one hand and philosophy on the other — two intellectual activities with different methodologies, different styles, and perhaps different subject matters — has a complex history which I shall not try to recapitulate. I wish only, as an introduction to a discussion of quantum mechanical holism, to remark that in recent decades, there seems to have been a moderate amount of recovery of the old unified discipline of natural philosophy. 20th century scientists have frequently cited classical philosophers not just for the sake of ornament but for the purpose of clarifying revolutionary ideas: e.g., Heisenberg (1962) cited Aristotle’s potentiality, d’Espagnat (1995) and others cited Kant’s distinction between the phenomenal and the noumenal, Wigner (1960) cited Peirce’s evolutionary theory of concept formation, Weyl (1970) cited Pythagoras on intellectual harmony, Stapp (1993) cited James’ holistic theory of consciousness, and Primas (1983) frequently refers to classical as well as contemporary philosophical literature.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  • Aerts D. and Daubechies I. (1978): Physical justification for using the tensor product to describe two quantum systems as a joint system. Helv. Phys. Acta 51, 661–675.

    MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Anselm (1945): Proslogium. In St Anselm, ed. and transl. by S.N. Deane (Open Court, La Salle), Chap. III.

    Google Scholar 

  • Diósi L. (1988): Quantum stochastic processes as models for state vector reduction. J. Phys. A 21, 2885–2898.

    Article  MathSciNet  ADS  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • d’Espagnat B. (1995): Veiled Reality (Addison-Wesley, Reading), p. 7.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gell-Mann M. and Hartle J.B. (1993): Classical equations for quantum systems. Phys. Rev. D 47, 3345–3382.

    Article  MathSciNet  ADS  Google Scholar 

  • Ghirardi G.C., Rimini A., and Weber T. (1986): Unified dynamics of microscopic and macroscopic systems. Phys. Rev. D 34, 470–491.

    Article  MathSciNet  ADS  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Gisin N. (1984): Quantum measurements and stochastic processes. Phys. Rev. Lett. 52, 1657–1660.

    Article  MathSciNet  ADS  Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths R. (1984): Consistent histories and the interpretation of quantum mechanics. J. Stat. Phys. 36, 219–272.

    Article  ADS  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Heisenberg W. (1962): Physics and Philosophy (Harper, New York), p. 53.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant I. (1781): Kritik der reinen Vernunft (Johann Friedrich Hartknoch, Riga). Transl. by N.K. Smith (Macmillan, London, 1990).

    Google Scholar 

  • Károlyházy F., Frenkel A., and Lukacs B. (1986): On the possible role of gravity in the reduction of the wave function. In Quantum Concepts of Space and Time, ed. by R. Penrose and C. Isham (Clarendon, Oxford), pp. 109–128.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leibniz G.W. (1947): Discourse on Metaphysics, transl. by G.R. Montgomery (Open Court, La Salle).

    Google Scholar 

  • Newton I. (1713): Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy (Royal Society, London). Transl. by A. Motte (1729), revised by F. Cajori (University of California Press, Berkeley, 1934).

    Google Scholar 

  • Newton I. (1717): Opticks (London, 2nd ed.). Reprinted 1952 (Dover, New York), Book III, Part I, p. 400.

    Google Scholar 

  • Neumann J. von (1932): Mathematische Grundlagen der Quantenmechanik (Springer, Berlin). Transl. by R.T. Beyer (Princeton University Press, Princeton, 1955).

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Omnès R. (1992): Consistent interpretations of quantum mechanics. Rev. Mod. Phys. 64, 339–382.

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  • Parmenides (1945): Selections from Early Greek Philosophy, ed. by M.C. Nahm (Crofts, New York, 2nd ed.), pp. 113–121.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pearle P. (1985): On the time it takes a state vector to reduce. J. Stat. Phys. 41, 719–727.

    Article  MathSciNet  ADS  Google Scholar 

  • Penrose R. 1989: The Emperor’s New Mind (Oxford University Press, Oxford), Chap. 8.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peres A. (1995): Quantum Theory: Concepts and Methods (Kluwer, Dordrecht), pp. 123–126, 147.

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Primas H. (1983): Chemistry, Quantum Mechanics, and Reductionism (Springer, Berlin, 2nd ed.).

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Primas H. (1990): Mathematical and philosophical questions in the theory of open and macroscopic quantum systems. In Sixty-two Years of Uncertainty: Historical, Philosophical, and Physical Inquiries into the Foundations of Quantum Mechanics, ed. by A.L Miller (Plenum, New York), pp. 233–257.

    Google Scholar 

  • Primas H. (1994): Endo-and exotheories of matter. In Inside Versus Outside, ed. by H. Atmanspacher and G.J. Dalenoort (Springer, Berlin), pp. 163–193.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Redhead M.L.G. (1987): Incompleteness, Nonlocality, and Realism: a Prolegomenon to the Philosophy of Quantum Mechanics (Clarendon, Oxford), Chap. 4.

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Schmidt E. (1907): Zur Theorie der linearen und nichtlinearen Integralgleichungen I, II. Mathematische Annalen 63, 433–476, 64, 161–174.

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Schrödinger E. (1926): Quantisierung als Eigenwertproblem IV. Annalen der Physik 81, 109–139.

    Article  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Schrödinger E. (1935a): Discussion of probability relations between separated systems. Proc. Cambridge Phil. Soc. 31, 555–562.

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  • Schrödinger E. (1935b): Die gegenwärtige Situation in der Quantenmechanik. Naturwissenschaften 23, 807–812, 823–828, 844–849.

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  • Schrödinger E. (1936): Probability relations between separated systems. Proc. Cambridge Phil. Soc. 32, 446–452.

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  • Shimony A. (1991): Desiderata for a modified quantum dynamics. PSA 1990 (Philosophy of Science Association, East Lansing), pp. 49–59. Reprinted in Shimony (1993), Vol. II, pp. 55–67.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shimony A. (1993): Search for a Naturalistic World View, Vols. I, II (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge).

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Spinoza B. (1677): Ethics, transl. by W.H. White and A.H. Stirling (Oxford University Press, Oxford, 1927).

    Google Scholar 

  • Stapp H. (1993): Mind, Matter, and Quantum Mechanics (Springer, Berlin), p. 135.

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Stein H. (1967): Newtonian space-time. Texas Quarterly 10, 174–200.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stein H. (1970): On the notion of field in Newton, Maxwell and beyond. In Historical and Philosophical Perspectives of Science (Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, Vol. 5), ed. by R. Steuwer (University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis), pp. 264–287, here: part I.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weyl H. (1970): Raum-Zeit-Materie (Springer, Berlin, 6th ed.), p. 317.

    Book  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Wigner E. (1960): The unreasonable effectiveness of mathematics in the natural sciences. Communications in Pure and Applied Mathematics 13, 222–237, here: p. 226.

    Article  Google Scholar 

References

  • Aspect A., Dalibard J., and Roger G. (1982): Experimental test of Bell’s inequalities using time-varying analyzers. Phys. Rev. Lett. 49, 1804–1807.

    Article  MathSciNet  ADS  Google Scholar 

  • Bell J.S. (1964): On the Einstein Podolsky Rosen paradox. Physics 1, 195–200.

    Google Scholar 

  • Primas H. (1993): The Cartesian cut, the Heisenberg cut, and disentangled observers. In Symposia on the Foundations of Modern Physics 1992. The Copenhagen Interpretation and Wolfgang Pauli, ed. by K.V. Laurikainen and C. Montonen (Singapore, World Scientific), pp. 245–269.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1999 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Shimony, A. (1999). Holism. In: Atmanspacher, H., Amann, A., Müller-Herold, U. (eds) On Quanta, Mind and Matter. Fundamental Theories of Physics, vol 102. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-011-4581-7_12

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-011-4581-7_12

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-94-010-5940-4

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-011-4581-7

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics