Skip to main content

Conflict Normalised

  • Chapter
Law and Reflexive Politics

Part of the book series: Law and Philosophy Library ((LAPS,volume 35))

  • 164 Accesses

Abstract

The argument that follows is the most difficult one to level against the republicans, because it aims to confront the republicans’most inspired moment, their debt to Critical Legal Studies, particularly that to Roberto Unger. Unger’s is a powerful version of the law-as-politics position, in so far as he vests in law the possibility of pursuing radical politics and of countering the ‘false necessity’ of the confinement of our political vision within rigid institutional assumptions. What puts him in the broad republican category here, is that he gives his politics legal leverage. Nothing, says Unger, compels us to reduce the political to the exclusive alternatives of ‘tinkering’ with the institutions or revolting against them.1 This disjunction blinkers the very real possibility that the political may draw its inspiration from the institutions’- significantly here law’s - own powerful imagination. Unger’s work in legal and social theory is the constant endeavour to do just that, to tap that imagination. This argument has for some time now been expounded by the Critical Legal School that seeks to upset the legal system’s tendency to assimilate the new to the old, its overwhelming of the innovative, its tendency to rationalise the incongruent into coherence, thus conspiring to the impoverishment of legal analysis through its foreclosure of broader conflict. In contrast, Critical Legal Analysis is geared to restoring ‘deviations and contradictions as intellectual and political opportunities rather than threats.’2 To resist the severing of legal analysis from broader conflicts, it will draw from the system itself to reveal suppressed possibilities by showing legal dogma to be incoherent, then playing up the ‘dangerous supplements’. Where the law exhibits the overwhelming tendency to assimilate the ‘deviant’ case within already existing schemata of processing it, the critical scholar will emphasise alternative possibilities, new relevancies that upset settled patterns. There is a strong continuity in Unger’s accounts of how this strategy of ‘dis-entrenchment’ and ‘re-construction’ is envisaged, going back to at least his CLS manifesto, 3 and variably described as ‘deviationist doctrine’,4 ‘negative capability’,5 and ‘mapping and criticism’.6 In each case, significantly, the same political logic of disruption draws from within the institution: as Unger put it in the Chorley lecture,7 his Critical Legal Theory understands the institution as law but undertakes it as politics.

Where theorists in earlier times were haunted by the fragility of order, [today theory] appears to suffer from a surfeit of order. And ultimately, ofcourse, the heroic metatheorist will suffer the fate; his agon will be routinized. (Wolin)

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 169.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. ‘In this way we can break a little further from the tedious, degrading rhythm of history-with its long lulls of collective narcolepsy punctuated by violent revolutionary seizures.’ (Unger, 1987b, 1)

    Google Scholar 

  2. Unger, 1996, 9

    Google Scholar 

  3. Unger (1983)

    Google Scholar 

  4. Unger, ibid., pp15ff

    Google Scholar 

  5. Unger, 1987b, pp 81, 156-157

    Google Scholar 

  6. Unger, 1996, pp20ff

    Google Scholar 

  7. Unger, ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  8. I have argued this at some length in Christodoulidis (1996)

    Google Scholar 

  9. See above, chapter eight

    Google Scholar 

  10. Luhmann, 1972, 74

    Google Scholar 

  11. Luhmann, 1984, 509

    Google Scholar 

  12. See chapter ten, above

    Google Scholar 

  13. Luhmann, 1984, 512

    Google Scholar 

  14. On examples of this see Heller, 1988, 187 and n. 15

    Google Scholar 

  15. On the transitory nature of conflict situations in law see also Broekman, 1989, 318

    Google Scholar 

  16. The degree to which the system is open to learning is, of course as always, an internal matter. In Luhmann’s terms this would be expressed in the following way: the system itself controls the balance of redundancy and variety. It is a distinction that bears on the system’s readiness to vary its structures in the face of an evolving environment. Variety is about increasing responsiveness, redundancy about suppressing the element of surprise in the system.

    Google Scholar 

  17. On this see Teubner, 1993, pp51-55 and for the critique of systems theory as neo-Darwinist, see Rottleutner, 1988, 97

    Google Scholar 

  18. Teubner, 1993, 51

    Google Scholar 

  19. Cf. Luhmann on the nature of the trial: conditions concern ‘the specification of the interaction system in preparation for a binding legal decision under previously established criteria instead of the general task or arbitration with consideration of all the relevant circumstances; the neutralisation of the judge’s individual personality as factor in decision-making; the removal of the orientation to one’s other roles for all involved parties …, ignoring public reactions, particularly the colere publique …; and finally a separation between court and procedure… For their part such differentiations require complex societal preconditions; for example those concerning contact mobility, degree of abstraction in the processing of experience, tolerance and indifference within social relations.’ (1972, 134-5) See also 1993, ch.6

    Google Scholar 

  20. Teubner, 1993a, pp59ff, but adjusts it to describe the relationship between a single interaction and society as a whole. What he retains from Habermas is the interface mechanism, the connecting process between the two.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Also Heller: ‘Litigation, when not simply a form of debt collection, is designed to upset legal practice, invoke the search for meaning in legal reason.’ (1988, 186 n.13)

    Google Scholar 

  22. Teubner, 1993, 62

    Google Scholar 

  23. Cf Neisser, 1976, pp20ff. Neisser calls these pre-conceptions ‘orienting schemata’ and they orient the observer within the cmplexity and equivocality of the immediately available environment by constructing certain expectations about relevant information.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Luhmann, 1971, 33

    Google Scholar 

  25. ibid

    Google Scholar 

  26. Luhmann, 1995, pp 285, 291

    Google Scholar 

  27. On confirmation and condensation, see S.C.Smith (1995)

    Google Scholar 

  28. Luhmann, 1995, 291

    Google Scholar 

  29. ibid

    Google Scholar 

  30. Luhmann, 1971, 34

    Google Scholar 

  31. Unger, 1996, 20

    Google Scholar 

  32. Luhmann, 1971, 85. The problem that is being identified here is that of providing the strategically correct stimulus that may make the idiosyncratic system respond in the desirable way, desirable, that is, in terms also of how the social environment will receive the legal decision. We have learnt from Teubner how precarious the process of this ’structural coupling’ between diverse fields is, how easily it can go wrong, how easily the logics of the systems can be abridged, boundaries overstepped (regulatory trilemma) (See Teubner, 1983, 239). But Teubner’s departure point is from problems of regulatory failure, whereas, for us, the question is different. It is about taking our conflict to law-conflict that arises from and informs spontaneous social contexts-and deciding whether or not we must pay the price that it be compromised, normalised.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Luhmann, 1989, 147. In other words, it relies on ‘bying into’ the discourse one wishes to confront, to go back to that dilemma described by Mathiesen some twenty years ago in (1974)

    Google Scholar 

  34. Luhmann, 1971, 33

    Google Scholar 

  35. Heller, 1988, p 197

    Google Scholar 

  36. ibid, 575

    Google Scholar 

  37. Unger, 1996, 19

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1998 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Christodoulidis, E.A. (1998). Conflict Normalised. In: Law and Reflexive Politics. Law and Philosophy Library, vol 35. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-011-3967-0_14

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-011-3967-0_14

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-1-4020-0283-0

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-011-3967-0

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics