Skip to main content

Conflict Severed

  • Chapter
  • 165 Accesses

Part of the book series: Law and Philosophy Library ((LAPS,volume 35))

Abstract

If the failure to draw the necessary distinctions between the two system referents conflated conflicts, republicanism is also guilty of ignoring the severing of conflict that this entails. The crux of this is that there occurs a severing of the connection between the broader conflict and what appears as the object of litigation. How the meaning of conflict changes as a consequence will be explored, in turn, along two dimensions, ‘material’ and’ social’.

Because collective action questions the system’s structural logic it is destined to reproduce itself beyond the forms of mediation that can interpret it. (Melucci)

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   169.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. According to the formulation of Fischer, 1964. Luhmann relies on this in his account of conflict in 1981, 110

    Google Scholar 

  2. ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Luhmann (1984)

    Google Scholar 

  4. On the relevant UK legislation see Davies & Freedland, 1984, pp, 798, 805-813

    Google Scholar 

  5. Brown, 1990, pp 134-135

    Google Scholar 

  6. Quoted in Brown, 1990, 139

    Google Scholar 

  7. Gusfield, 1963

    Google Scholar 

  8. Notwithstanding the affinity of this politics, in the case Gusfield describes, with specifically conservative concerns for the maintainance of group status.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Brown, 1990, 147

    Google Scholar 

  10. For another see Smith S C, 1991, 329-331

    Google Scholar 

  11. Brown, 1993, 164

    Google Scholar 

  12. Brown, 1990, 142

    Google Scholar 

  13. Sartre, 1976, pp256ff

    Google Scholar 

  14. Willener, 1970, passim and 281-98. Willener argues that at the period of upheaval the emergent (instituant) had only the most tenuous links with the established (institue). Of the two elements that Melucci identifies as characterising the ideology of the movement, the first is ‘the negation of the gap between expectations and reality. The birth of a movement is marked by “moments of madness” when all things seem possible … Ideology thus overcomes the inadequacy of action.’ (1992, 133)

    Google Scholar 

  15. Touraine, 1981, 30

    Google Scholar 

  16. Touraine’s theory invites critique at least as to the definition of social movement it advances. Touraine reserves the term Social movement for too broad a category of action since he uses it to cover the whole field of conflictual collective action.

    Google Scholar 

  17. The theory is susceptible to criticism on the identification of the action of social movements with class struggle. The class nature of social movements is at least questionable. For example the student struggles of the 60s and 70s did not in themselves embody class struggles but rather assumed the role of catalyst through worker-student contacts and alliances intended to mobilise the ‘true’ class actors. Melucci has challenged this aspect of his teacher’s work (1989, 80)

    Google Scholar 

  18. Touraine, 1981, 77

    Google Scholar 

  19. ibid., 81

    Google Scholar 

  20. Although the latter may seem to overstate the case for social movements, it remains crucially important to be able to identify what constitutes a stake adequate to uphold a social movement. This must be more comprehensive than the partial demands advanced at various stages of the conflict. It is a matter of distinguishing (middle range) strategic aims from the stake itself. To give an example, the middle-range targets of the student struggles of the late 60s in France and 70s in Germany, were the authoritarian way universities were run, the lack of student representation in the decision-making bodies, the prospect of unemployment, etc. It would be a mistake to identify these as the stakes of the movement. The student movement also and explicitly challenged the social utilisation of knowledge in the way the normative structures of their society supported it, and in that sense even advanced a counter-model for society. What is in doubt is whether we can call this the new site of class conflict in the way Touraine does, but what is not in doubt is that the stakes of a struggle, if it is to uphold a movement, must be identified at the more comprehensive level.

    Google Scholar 

  21. The point has been elaborated by Melucci (1982)

    Google Scholar 

  22. Touraine, 1981, ch.5, and 1977, pp310-325

    Google Scholar 

  23. Touraine, 1981, 84

    Google Scholar 

  24. Cf Teubner, 1989, 729, for the mode of that emergence in self-reference. Teubner describes how the capacity for collective action emerges when organised collectivities produce actions and then organised action feeds back to produce collective identity. See also his 1988a, 137-138: “It is … communication on its own identity and capacity for action that constitutes the corporate actor or collectivity as a mere semantic artifact, as a linguistically condensed perception of group identity. It is only to the extent that such a corporate actor becomes institutionalized, ie that organizational actions are actually oriented round this self-description, that the corporate actor takes on social reality.” (137-138) This indeed appears to me correct and insightful. But there is an ambivalence in Teubner’s paper that makes his argument occasionally baffling and does not live up to his own presupposition of the radically constructivist nature if the legal person. The ambivalence is relevant to his demarcating the “social substration of the legal person”. Teubner here spends a lot of time trying to find an adequate description of the social reality underlying the legal person, and, having discarded both individuals and groups as such, names it as a communicative process on which, and this is important, the legal reality superimposes itself and reworks to the extent that the two are no longer “identical” (138) in any possible sense. But in what sense is the social substration a communicative process in its own right at all? I think it cannot be. Because the communication underlying the law-albeit organisational or interactional-and “strictly coupled” by it into the law’s own idiom, has its own boundaries around its own topics and own self-descriptions. If that is so, the social substration of the legal person is thus not co-terminous with the legal person, and if it is not, it cannot be a substration. The law’s selectivity is constitutive of its “substration”; the law enacts into being its own “surrogate” environment-including its social “substration” through its own editing. It is thus impossible for the observer to demarcate an area of communication to serve as substratum that precedes what area of social communication the legal institution itself selects as constituting its substratum. The law is always already there before its social substratum. My objection to Teubner then is that in this paper he too goes down the same line of inquiry as the theories he rejects, and that he rejects the theories on the basis that they have found something wrong not that they have gone about looking for it in the wrong way. His methodology here concedes too much and undermines the crux of his substantive argument.

    Google Scholar 

  25. As Sullivan writes in her defence of partiality, ‘[Intermediate organizations not only facilitate individual self-definition and expression but also keep the state from replicating itself by nurturing deviance, diversity and dissent. These functions depend on subgroups’ private status-on their detachment and distance from the all-inclusive State.’ (Sullivan, 1988, 1721)

    Google Scholar 

  26. Melucci, 1992, 137. Melucci explains the interdependence in similar terms to Touraine (note the proximity of the following exposition with Touraine): ‘The meaning of collective action, which is to be found in the system of relations of which the actor is a part, is identified with the particular point of view of the individual actor: the field of social relationships, which is always made up of a network of tensions and oppositions, is restructured according to the position occupied by the actor … The adversary is seen as only having a negative relationship to the totality: the adversary is in fact the very obstacle that prevents general needs from being satisfied, or general goals from being attained … It is, then, always possible to identify in the ideology of a social movement a definition of the social actor who is mobilized, of the adversary against whom the movement must struggle, and of the collective objectives of the struggle.’ (1992, 132)

    Google Scholar 

  27. Melucci, 1989, 29. Melucci provides abundant empirical evidence of such forms of collective identity-generation through expressive activities in (1989)

    Google Scholar 

  28. Eder writes: ‘Theories of social movements assume that the self-description of the collective actor as a social movement places him beyond the institutional framework.’ (1993, 60) But cf. Turner here, who argues that social movements are “inevitably [!] movements about the rights of citizenship: (1986, 92)

    Google Scholar 

  29. Simmel, 1954, pp98-101

    Google Scholar 

  30. Coser, 1956, 38

    Google Scholar 

  31. ibid., 151

    Google Scholar 

  32. Quoted in Coser, 1965, 1

    Google Scholar 

  33. Coser, 1956, 155

    Google Scholar 

  34. ibid., 80

    Google Scholar 

  35. Coser discusses their argument in 1956, 75ff

    Google Scholar 

  36. Note that I am not for a moment suggesting any blanket formula for community, a name that has been given to as diverse groupings as those which share, among others, a paradigm (Kuhn), a nomos (Cover), a culture, or a world-view (Goodman). My argument pivots on the’ sharing’ and allows the ‘what’ to be designated reflexively by those whose sharing of it appears significant and adequate to their sense of togetherness.

    Google Scholar 

  37. Virally, e.g., describes law as a force of collective integration in 1960, 21 Off. For an overview of theories and debates on the integrative function of law see Cotterrell, 1984, 73-103

    Google Scholar 

  38. 347 U.S. 383(1954)

    Google Scholar 

  39. It is problematical for the republicans in that the period of popular mobilisation did not, as they would have it, feed the new understanding of equality into law. And Ackerman needs to rely on a previous constitutional moment to justify the reasoning in the case, not the civil rights moment that had not yet occurred.

    Google Scholar 

  40. For Ackerman only the first of the moments, the ‘Reconstruction’, is a full-blown constitutional one. The second is a compelling synthesis of the Reconstruction moment with the New Deal moment of activist government (1991, pp 140-141). It is thus a prime example of what Ackerman calls ‘intergenerational synthesis’ by the Court. The third moment is a minor constitutional one because it does not fulfill all the necessary criteria Ackerman identifies. The civil rights movement is more or less a late expression of the New Deal constitutional moment. What matters for present purposes however is that there exists in Ackerman’s account an intimate feedback, a dialectic, between legal understanding and direct political popular mobilisation. And that the political voices calling for inclusion and equality carried into law and forced a revision of fundamental legal understandings.

    Google Scholar 

  41. 1986, 387ff

    Google Scholar 

  42. ‘Jurisgeneration’ for Cover is the process of giving birth to meaning within community but the community he is talking about is bound to a normative universe (a nomos) that is discrete, insular and specific. Cover makes this point over and over again. ‘The nomos that I have described requires no state.’ (11) His community is not a part of but an alternative to the state. (Cover, 1983) For more on Cover, see chapter sixteen.

    Google Scholar 

  43. Michelman, 1988, 1513-1514

    Google Scholar 

  44. For the connection of Michelman’s theory with Habermas’s see part I

    Google Scholar 

  45. Michelman, 1988, 1529

    Google Scholar 

  46. ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  47. ‘Fear of the Negro … is a means of keeping the status system intact, of rallying all members of the white group around its standards.’ Because if the Negro is seen as dangerous, ‘those in the white group who befriend him can be effectively characterized as “renegades” endangering the very existence of the white group.’ (Coser, 1954, p 109). For the facets of fear and the function in maintaining the white group’s identity, see indicatively, Mydral (1944). Tannenbaum describes it thus: ‘The South gives indications of being afraid of the Negro. I do not mean physical fear. It is not a matter of cowardice or bravery; it is something deeper and more fundamental. It is fear of losing grip upon the world.’ (Tannenbaum, 1924, pp 8-9)

    Google Scholar 

  48. Historically there is abundant evidence of this danger. And the republicans can celebrate the Constitutional moment only at the expense of downplaying the often successful resistance ‘within’ the new community. Even the most widely celebrated republican moment of ‘Reconstruction’ is conceived as a birth of a new community only by downplaying the successful white Southern resistance to the practices of Reconstruction that profoundly altered not only the nature of the objectives of the ‘Radical Republicans’ (Ackerman’s critical constitutional vanguard) but also the depth of implementation and ultimately the constitutional form of the ensuing era. (On this see Foner E (1988)). As Simon stresses, ‘[a]t a minimum the Redeemers must be seen as achieving a special status for the South as “a distinct society” within the new constitutional order of the Union … The same forces that galvanized the Reconstruction Republicans also mobilized couter-revolutionary forces in both sections of the country that sought to find ways of channeling and eventually dissipating the Reconstruction effort.’(1992, 510, 512)

    Google Scholar 

  49. I owe this point to Maurice Glasman. It relates to the argument that McIntyre makes about ‘epistemological crises’ that come about when narratives can no longer rationalise the unexpected. (Mclntyre, 1977).

    Google Scholar 

  50. See Christodoulidis, 1994, 11-12

    Google Scholar 

  51. Michelman, 1986, 32

    Google Scholar 

  52. Sherry, 1986, 615

    Google Scholar 

  53. Michelman, 1986, 4

    Google Scholar 

  54. ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  55. In discussing the ‘emancipatory activity of Black Americans,’ Michelman asks: ‘Does anybody doubt that the judicial agents of the challengers’ accumulating citizenship drew on interpretive possibilities that the challengers’own activity was helping to create?’ (1988, 1527)

    Google Scholar 

  56. Piccioto, 1979, 171-172

    Google Scholar 

  57. Dworkin, 1986, 190

    Google Scholar 

  58. This is not strikingly different from the old position in favour of common law that argues that judges express the mores of the community. On this see Lindsay Farmer’s excellent (1993)

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1998 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Christodoulidis, E.A. (1998). Conflict Severed. In: Law and Reflexive Politics. Law and Philosophy Library, vol 35. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-011-3967-0_13

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-011-3967-0_13

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-1-4020-0283-0

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-011-3967-0

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics