Skip to main content

Part of the book series: Contributions To Phenomenology ((CTPH,volume 7))

  • 52 Accesses

Abstract

For centuries, one of the staples of Western thought has been a rather specific conception of what a human person is. On this conception, the person is understood, as Clifford Geertz has put it, as “a bounded, unique, more or less integrated motivational and cognitive universe, a dynamic center of awareness, emotion, judgment and action organized into a distinctive whole and set contrastively both against other such wholes and against a social and natural background.”1 Though Descartes was by no means the father of this conception of the human person, the self, the Cartesian cogito provided it with a powerful and influential articulation. In the wake of Descartes, Enlightenment thought in its various dresses has often exalted the self to quasi-divine status, or at least ascribed to it an angelic independence from the physical and cultural context in which it acts.

James Bernauer’s comments on earlier version of this essay were most helpful.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. Cliffort Geertz, “From the Native's Point of View,” in Interpretive Social Science, ed. Paul Rabinow and William M. Sullivan (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1979), 229.

    Google Scholar 

  2. See Anthony Giddens, Central Problems in Social Theory (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1979) 29. Hereafter cited as CP.

    Google Scholar 

  3. See Louis Althusser and Etienne Balibar, Reading Capital (London: New Left Books, 1970), 180-189. “The structure is immanent in its effects in the Spinozist sense of the term,..the whole existence of the structure consists of its effects …. [The structure] is merely a specific combination of its particular elements, is nothing outside its effects”(188-189). For a good overview of this and other continental analyses which claim to undercut the distinctiveness of the self, see CP, 9-48.

    Google Scholar 

  4. See Samuel Ijsseling, “Hermeneutics and Textuality,” Research in Phenomenology 9 (1979): 10.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Anthony Kenny defended this position in the untitled paper he read at the “Continental and Anglo-American Philosophy: A New Relationship?” conference at the University of Chicago, May 11-13, 1984. See also G.E.M. Anscombe, “The First Person,” in Mind and Language ed. S. Guttenplan (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1975) 59.

    Google Scholar 

  6. CP, 70.

    Google Scholar 

  7. CP, 55-56.

    Google Scholar 

  8. See William Wimsatt, “Robustness, Reliability, and Multiple Determination in Science,” in Scientific Inquiry and the Social Sciences, ed. Marilyn M. Brewer and Barry E. Collins (San Francisco: Jossey-Bass, 1981) 124-163, esp. 126-128. Hereafter cited as RR.

    Google Scholar 

  9. RR, 144-147.

    Google Scholar 

  10. See Martin Heidegger, Being and Time, tr. John Maquarrie and Edward Robinson (New York: Harper and Row, 1962) 67-69. Hereafter cited as BT.

    Google Scholar 

  11. BT, 68. See also Heidegger, The Metaphysical Foundation of Logic tr. Michael Hein (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1984) 188-189. Hereafter cited as FL.

    Google Scholar 

  12. BT, 303.

    Google Scholar 

  13. BT, 308.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Heidegger, “Was Heisst Denken?” in Vorträge und Aufsätze (Pfullingen: Neske, 1967), Vol. 2, 3; Basic Writings, ed. David Krell (New York: Harper and Row, 1977) 345.

    Google Scholar 

  15. See Alasdair MacIntyre, After Virtue (Notre Dame: Notre Dame University Press, 1981), 96-97. Hereafter cited as, AV

    Google Scholar 

  16. AV, 89. My insertion.

    Google Scholar 

  17. AV, 91.

    Google Scholar 

  18. See Paul Ricoeur, The Rule of Metaphor, tr. Robert Czerny with Kathleen McLaughlin and John Costello (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1977) 7. Hereafter cited as RM.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Ricoeur himself suggests something of this “rebound” effect. See RM, 87-89.

    Google Scholar 

  20. See in this connection Hannah Arendt, “The Concept of History: Ancient and Modern,” in her Between Past and Future (New York: Viking Press, 1965). Hereafter cited as PF.

    Google Scholar 

  21. For a discussion of this issue from another angle, see my “Authors, Audiences and Texts,“ Human Studies (1982) 137-146.

    Google Scholar 

  22. H.-N. Castaneda, “On the Phenomeno-Logic of the I,” Akten des XIV Internationalen Kongresses für Philosophie, Wien, 1968, 261. Husserl, it should be recalled here, speaks of the “primal ‘I’ … which can never lose its uniqueness and indeclinability.” See his The Crisis of European Sciences and Transcendental Phenomenology, tr. David Carr (Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 1970) 185. Hereafter cited as TC.

    Google Scholar 

  23. TC, 266.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Colin McGinn, The Subjective View (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1983) 53–55. Hereafter cited as SV. He explicitly criticizes here G.E.M. Ancombe's position referred to above, and thereby implicitly attacks the Kenny thesis I have mentioned.

    Google Scholar 

  25. SV, 91.

    Google Scholar 

  26. SV, 91.

    Google Scholar 

  27. SV, 91 fn. 32.

    Google Scholar 

  28. SV, 93.

    Google Scholar 

  29. McGinn does deal, under another heading, with the dimension with which I am concerned. He recognizes that his position poses problems for physicalist accounts of experience. He himself, though, does defend a specific version of physicalism. See SV, 137-145.

    Google Scholar 

  30. This argument parallels MacIntyre's contention, discussed above, that a full account of determinism would have to be couched in a “neutral” language, but that no such neutral language is either available or in prospect.

    Google Scholar 

  31. See in this connection Richard Bauman, Let Your Words Be Few (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1983) 14. Hereafter cited as YW.

    Google Scholar 

  32. See in this connection, Paul Ricoeur, Interpretation Theory (Fort Worth: TCU Press, 1976) 22.

    Google Scholar 

  33. The possibility of shifting emphasis between the topic and the audience also makes possible the historical distinction between rhetoric and science. However much one might today want to attenuate this distinction, it is hard to claim that all discourse has the same manifest emphasis. Styles of discourse differ from one another and are deployed at the discretion of the speaker.

    Google Scholar 

  34. YW, 10-11 and 30.

    Google Scholar 

  35. For more detailed argument, see my Silence: The Phenomenon and Its Ontological Significance (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1980), esp. 54-82. Arendt makes a comparable point in terms of thinking and its independence from space-time. See PF, 13.

    Google Scholar 

  36. Heidegger, The Basic Problems of Phenomenology, tr. Albert Hofstradter (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1982) 171. See also H-G. Gadamer, Philosophical Hermeneutics, tr. David E. Linge (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1976). Gadamer says: “Self-understanding only realizes itself in the understanding of a subject-matter and does not have the character of a free self-realization” (55).

    Google Scholar 

  37. Emmanuel Mounier makes something of this same point from another standpoint. See his Personalism, tr. Phillip Mairet (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1952) 39, 59-64.

    Google Scholar 

  38. CP, 56-57.

    Google Scholar 

  39. CP, 84.

    Google Scholar 

  40. For an interesting account of the self, see Edward Ballard's Man and Technology: Toward the Measurement of Culture (Pittsburgh: Duquesne University Press, 1978) esp. 124-129, and his Principles of Interpretation (Athens: Ohio University Press, 1983), esp 216-225. See also FL, 139.

    Google Scholar 

  41. My conclusions about selves mesh well with those reached by Paul Ri-coeur in his Soi-même comme un autre (Paris: Editions du Seuil, 1990).

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1991 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Dauenhauer, B.P. (1991). I and Mine. In: Elements of Responsible Politics. Contributions To Phenomenology, vol 7. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-011-3564-1_6

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-011-3564-1_6

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-94-010-5579-6

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-011-3564-1

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics