Skip to main content

Defining the Organism in the Welfare State: The Politics of Individuality in American Culture, 1890–1950

  • Chapter
Biology as Society, Society as Biology: Metaphors

Part of the book series: Sociology of the Sciences ((SOSC,volume 18))

Abstract

To speak of the “transfer of metaphors between biology and the social sciences” implies a sense of movement from one space into another. Implicit is an understanding of dichotomy, of boundaries to be transgressed. Framing the problem in this way legitimates the disciplinary boundaries central to the professional identity of the biological and social sciences and to their professional authority within the public sphere. For example, one might detail the preponderance of anthropomorphic terms such as “spite” and “slavery” in sociobiology, citing how such transgressions erode the disciplinary authority of the social sciences and breach the nature/nurture divide. Instead of reifying these boundaries, can we bring them into question? Can we alter these disciplinary topographies, shattering the linear movement of words from one space to another, and situate the metaphors within a general field of meaning? Once we begin to explore science as culture, the dichotomy erected between the biological and the social begins to break down. In the subject matter of this essay, biology is a human science.1

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. The treatment of biology as human science in the twentieth century has been most systematically explored by Donna Haraway, Primate Visions: Gender, Race, and Natural in the World of Modern Science (London: Routledge, 1989); Stephen J.Cross and William R. Albury, “Walter B. Canon. L. J. Henderson, and the Organic Analogy,” Osiris, 2d. ser., 3 (1987), 165 – 192; and Robert M. Young, “The Naturalization of Value Systems in the Human Sciences,” in Science and Belief: Darwin to Einstein, Block VI, Problem in the Bioloical and Human Sciences(Milton Keynes: Opem University Press, 1981), pp. 63-110.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Sam B. Girgus, The Law of the Heart: Individualism and the Modern Self in American Literature (Austin: University of Texas Press, 1979), p. 12.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Isaiah Berlin, “Two Concepts of Liberty,” in Michael Sandel (ed.), Liberalism and Its Critics (New York: New York University Press, 1984), p. 17.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Sandel (ed.), Liberalism and Its Critics, p. 6.

    Google Scholar 

  5. William Corlett, Community Without Unity: A Politics of Derridian Extravagance (Durham: Duke University Press, 1989), p. 23.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Leo W. Buss, The Evolution of Individuality (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1987), p. 13.

    Google Scholar 

  7. On this inversion of liberal in American social science, see Dorothy Ross, The Origins of American Social Science (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1991). The development of an interdependent market economy and its impact on the rise of professional American social science is treated at length in Thomas L. Haskell, The Emergence of Professional Social Science: The American Social Association and the Nineteenth-Century Crisis of Authority (Urbana: University of Illinois Press, 1977).

    Google Scholar 

  8. For a historical analysis of the “common good” in American political rhetoric, see Rodgers, Contested Truths.

    Google Scholar 

  9. T. J. Jackson Lears, No Place of Grace: Antimodernism and the Transformation of American Culture (New York: Pantheon Books, 1981), p. 37. See, also, T. J. Jackson Lears, “From Salvation to Self-Realization: Advertising and the Therapeutic Roots of the Consumer Culture, 1880–1930,” in Richard Wightman Fox and T. J. Jackson Lears (eds.), The Culture of Consumption: Critical Essays in American History, 1880–1980 (New York: Pantheon, 1983), pp. 1–38. For a somewhat different perspective on the reconstruction of self in relation to an emerging consumer culture in America, see Casey Nelson Blake, Beloved Community: The Cultural Criticism of Randolph Bourne, Van Wyck Brooks, Waldo Frank & Lewis Mumford (Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1990).

    Google Scholar 

  10. Ross, The Origins of American Social Science, p. 237.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Quoted in Robert B. Westbrook, John Dewey and American Democracy (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1991), p. 44.

    Google Scholar 

  12. John Dewey, “The Reflex Arc Concept in Psychology” (1896) in The Early Works of John Dewey, 1882–1895 (Carbondale, Ill.: Southern Illinois University Press, 1972), Vol. 5, p. 97.

    Google Scholar 

  13. John Dewey, “Evolution and Ethics,” in The Early Works of John Dewey 5 (1898), 53.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Westbrook, John Dewey, p. 43.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Norton Wise provides a fascinating analysis of the emergence of ideas on statistical causality in the context of individualism and its relationship to Gemeinschaft and Gesellschaft in central European culture from 1870 to 1920. His approach strikes a resonant chord with some of the themes raised in this essay. See M. Norton Wise, “How Do Sums Count? On the Cultural Origins of Statistical Causality,” in Lorenz Krüger, Gerd Gigerenzer, and Mary S. Morgan (eds.), The Probabilistic Revolution. Vol. 1: Ideas in History (Cambridge: MIT Press, 1987).

    Google Scholar 

  16. Charles Otis Whitman, “Specialization and Organization, Companion Principles of All Progress — The Most Important Needs of American Biology,” Biological lectures Delivered at the Marine Biological Laboratory of Woods Hole (1891), pp. 1–2. On Whitman, see Edward S. Morse, “Charles Otis Whitman,” National Academy of Sciences Biographical Memoirs 7 (1912), 269–288; Frank R. Lillie, “Charles Otis Whitman,” Journal of Morphology 22 (1911), xv–lxxvii; Jane Maienschein, introduction to Defining Biology. Lectures from the 1890s (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1986); idem., “Whitman at Chicago: Establishing a Chicago Style of Biology?” in Ronald Rainger, Keith R. Benson, and Jane Maienschein (eds.), The American Development of Biology (Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 1988), pp. 151–182.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Whitman, “Specialization and Organization,” pp. 6–7.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Whitman, “Specialization and Organization,”, p. 23.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Jane Addams, “The Subjective Necessity for Social Settlements,” in Henry C. Adams (ed.), Philanthropy and Social Progress (New York, 1893), p. 4. On the search for community in late nineteenth-century America, see, for example.

    Google Scholar 

  20. J. Ronald Engel, Sacred Sands: The Struggle for Community in the Indiana Dunes (Middletown, Conn.: Wesleyan University Press, 1983).

    Google Scholar 

  21. Jean B. Quandt, From the Small Town to the Great Community: The Social Thought of Progressive Intellectuals (New Brunswick, N.J.: Rutgers University Press, 1970).

    Google Scholar 

  22. Wiebe, The Search for Order, 1877–1920

    Google Scholar 

  23. R. Jackson Wilson, In Quest of Community: Social Philosophy in the United State, 1860–1920 (New York: Oxford University Press, 1968).

    Google Scholar 

  24. Whitman, “Specialization and Organization,” pp. 23, 9.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Whitman, “Specialization and Organization,”, pp. 22, 25. Both Maienschein, “Whitman at Chicago,” and Philip J. Pauly, “Summer Resort and Scientific Discipline: Woods Hole and the Structure of American Biology, 1882–1925,” in The American Development of Biology, pp. 121–150 emphasize this organizational ideal in Whitman’s work. Pauly has also emphasized the MBL as a place of community for a nascent tradition of American biology.

    Google Scholar 

  26. Charles Otis Whitman, “The Inadequacy of the Cell-Theory of Development,” Journal of Morphology 8 (1893), 641.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  27. Charles Otis Whitman, “The Inadequacy of the Cell-Theory of Development,” Journal of Morphology 8 (1893), p. 648.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  28. Charles Otis Whitman, “The Inadequacy of the Cell-Theory of Development,” Journal of Morphology 8 (1893), pp. 646, 653.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  29. Whitman, “Inadequacy of the Cell Theory,” pp. 645, 657.

    Google Scholar 

  30. See, e.g., Daniel Pick, Faces of Degeneration: A European Disorder, c. 1848–c. 1918 (Cambridge: Cambridge Univ. Press, 1989). For a historical account of regeneration studies in biology during this period, see Jane Maienschein, “T. H. Morgan’s Regeneration, Epigenesis and (W)holism,” in Charles Dinsmore (ed.), History of Regeneration Research (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991) and Gregg Mitman and Anne Fausto-Sterling, “Whatever Happened to Planaria? C. M. Child and the Physiology of Inheritance,” in Adele Clarke and Joan Fujimura (eds.), The Right Tools for the Job: At Work in Twentieth-Century Life Sciences (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1992), pp. 172–197.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  31. C. M. Child, Individuality in Organisms (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1915), p. 41.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  32. C. M. Child, “Behavior Origins From a Physiologic Point of View,” American Medical Association Archives of Neurology and Psychiatry 15 (1926), 174.

    Google Scholar 

  33. For a slightly different contextual analysis of Child’s theory of individuality in relation to liberalism and Chicago pragmatism, see Sharon Kingsland, “Toward a Natural History of the Human Psyche: Charles Manning Child, Charles Judson Herrick, and the Dynamic View of the Individual at the University of Chicago,” in Keith R. Benson, Ronald Rainger, and Jane Maienschein (eds.), The Expansion of American Biology (New Brunswick, N.J.: Rutgers University Press, 1991), pp. 195-230.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Samuel Jackson Holmes, “The Problem of Form Regulation,” Archives für Entwicklungmechanik 17 (1904), 265–304.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  35. S. J. Holmes, “Regulation as Functional Adjustment,” Journal of Experimental Zoology 4 (1904), 422.

    Google Scholar 

  36. C. M. Child, “The Physiological Basis of Restitution of Lost Parts,” Journal of Experimental Zoology 5 (1908), 497.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  37. Child, Individuality in Organisms, p. 22.

    Google Scholar 

  38. Child, Individuality in Organisms, pp. 21, 27.

    Google Scholar 

  39. C. M. Child, “Biological Foundations of Social Integration,” American Sociological Society Publications 22 (1928), 35.

    Google Scholar 

  40. S. I. Benn, “Individuality, Autonomy, and Community,” in Eugene Kamenka (ed.), Community as a Social Idea (New York: St. Martin’s Press, 1982), p. 55.

    Google Scholar 

  41. William E. Ritter, The Unity of the Organism, 2 vols. (Boston: Richard G. Badger, 1919), Vol. 1, pp. 14, 163.

    Google Scholar 

  42. Ritter, Unity of the Organism 1: 185–186. For a history of the symbiosis controversy, see Jan Sapp, “Symbiosis in Evolution: An Origin Story,” Endocytobiosis and Cell Research 7 (1990), 5–36.

    Google Scholar 

  43. Ritter, Unity of the Organism 2: 158–160.

    Google Scholar 

  44. Ritter, Unity of the Organism 2, pp. 353–357. For an analysis of American biologists’ response to World War I and their anti-war evolutionism.

    Google Scholar 

  45. Gregg Mitman, “Evolution as Gospel: William Patten, the Language of Democracy, and the Great War,” Isis 81 (1990), 446–463; idem., The State of Nature: Ecology, Community, and American Social Thought, 1900–1950 (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1992).

    Article  Google Scholar 

  46. Ritter, Unity of the Organism 2: 186.

    Google Scholar 

  47. John Dewey, “The Need for a Recovery of Philosophy,” in Creative Intelligence: Essays in the Pragmatic Attitude (New York: Henry Holt & Co., 1917), p. 10.

    Google Scholar 

  48. Ritter, Unity of the Organism 2: 306.

    Google Scholar 

  49. Ritter, Unity of the Organism 2, p. 353.

    Google Scholar 

  50. Quoted in Rodgers, Contested Truths, p. 204. On community as a cultural ideal in the 1930s, see Blake, Beloved Community, Richard H. Pells, Radical Visions and American Dreams: Culture and Social Thought in the Depression Years (1973. reprint, Middletown, Conn.: Wesleyan University Press, 1984).

    Google Scholar 

  51. For biographical accounts of Conklin’s life, see Garland E. Allen, “Edwin Grant Conklin, Dictionary of Scientific Biography 3: 389–391

    Google Scholar 

  52. E. Newton Harvey, “Edwin Grant Conklin,” National Academy of Sciences Biographical Memoirs 31 (1958), 54–91. For historical analyses of Conklin’s biological research and his public science.

    Google Scholar 

  53. J. W. Atkinson, “E. G. Conklin on Evolution: The Popular Writings of an Embryologist,” Journal of the History of Biology 18 (1985), 31–50

    Article  Google Scholar 

  54. Jane Maienschein, Transforming Traditions in American Biology, 1880–1915 (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1991).

    Google Scholar 

  55. Edwin Grant Conklin, Heredity and Environment in the Development of Men (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1915), p. 176. On Conklin’s belief in the importance of cytoplasm in heredity, see Maienschein, Transforming Traditions; Jan Sapp, Beyond the Gene: Cytoplasmic Inheritance and the Struggle for Authority in Genetics (New York: Oxford University Press, 1987).

    Google Scholar 

  56. E. G. Conklin, “The Basis of Individuality in Organisms from the Standpoint of Cytology and Embryology,” Science 43 (1916), 526.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  57. E. G. Conklin, “Biology and Democracy,” Scribner’s Magazine 65 (April, 1919), 410.

    Google Scholar 

  58. E. G. Conklin, “Biology and Democracy,” Scribner’s Magazine 65 (April, 1919), 407.

    Google Scholar 

  59. Conklin, Heredity and Environment, p. 484.

    Google Scholar 

  60. Conklin, “Biology and Democracy,” p. 408.

    Google Scholar 

  61. Conklin, “Biology and Democracy,”, pp. 407, 408.

    Google Scholar 

  62. Hamilton Cravens, The Triumph of Evolution: The Heredity-Environment Controversy, 1900–1941 (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1978); Haraway, Primate Visions, pp. 197–203.

    Google Scholar 

  63. E. G. Conklin, The Direction of Human Evolution, rev. ed. (New York: Charles Scribner’s Sons, 1934), pp. 145–146.

    Google Scholar 

  64. E. G. Conklin, The Direction of Human Evolution, rev. ed. (New York: Charles Scribner’s Sons, 1934), p. 149.

    Google Scholar 

  65. Conklin, “Biology and Democracy,” p. 407.

    Google Scholar 

  66. Michael Kammen, Spheres of Liberty: Changing Perceptions of Liberty in American Culture (Madison: University of Wisconsin Press, 1986), p. 151.

    Google Scholar 

  67. Herman Belz, “Changing Conceptions of Constitutionalism in the Era of World War II and the Cold War,” Journal of American History 59 (1972), 657.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  68. David Riesman, Individualism Reconsidered and Other Essays (Glencoe, Ill.: Free Press, 1954), p. 37.

    Google Scholar 

  69. David Riesman, Reuel Denney, and Nathan Glazer, The Lonely Crowd: A Study in Changing American Character (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1950). On the revival of individualism in 1950s American culture, see Booth, Believing Skeptics.

    Google Scholar 

  70. Richard H. Pells, The Liberal Mind in the Conservative Age: American Intellectuals in the 1940s & 1950s (New York: Harper & Row, 1985).

    Google Scholar 

  71. Frederic E. Clements and Ralph W. Chaney, Environment and Life in the Great Plains (Washington, D. C: Carnegie Institution of Washington, 1936), pp. 51–52.

    Google Scholar 

  72. Ronald C. Tobey, Saving the Prairies: The Life Cycle of the Founding School of American Plant Ecology, 1895–1955 (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1981). On Clement’s importance in the history of plant ecology.

    Google Scholar 

  73. Joel B. Hagen, “Organism and Environment: Frederic Clements’s Vision of a Unified Physiological Ecology,” in Ronald Rainger, Keith R. Benson, and Jane Maienschein (eds.), The American Development of Biology (Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 1988), pp. 257–280.

    Google Scholar 

  74. Robert P. Mcintosh, The Background of Ecology: Concept and Theory (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1985).

    Book  Google Scholar 

  75. Donald Worster, Nature’s Economy: The Roots of Ecology (San Francisco: Sierra Club Books, 1977). For a more detailed analysis of ecology’s debt to a nonhereditarian view of the organism, see Mitman, The State of Nature.

    Google Scholar 

  76. Henry Allen Gleason, “The Individualistic Concept of the Plant Association,” Bulletin of the Torrey Botanical Club 53 (1926), 16. On the revival of Gleason’s views in postwar American ecology, see T. F. H. Allen, Gregg Mitman, and T. W. Hoekstra, “Synthesis Mid-Century: J. T. Curtis and the Community Concept,” Journal of the Wisconsin Academy of Arts and Sciences (forthcoming).

    Google Scholar 

  77. Robert P. McIntosh, “H. A. Gleason — Individualistic Ecologist’ 1882–1975: His Contributions to Ecological Theory,” Bulletin of the Torrey Botanical Club 102 (1975), 253–73.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  78. Malcolm Nicolson, “Henry Allen Gleason and the Individualistic Hypothesis: The Structure of a Botanist’s Carrer,” Botancial Review 2 (1990), 91–161.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  79. Dorian Sagan and Lynn Margulis, “Epilogue: The Uncut Self,” in Alfred I. Tauber (ed.), Organism and the Origins of Self (Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1991), p. 365.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1995 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Mitman, G. (1995). Defining the Organism in the Welfare State: The Politics of Individuality in American Culture, 1890–1950. In: Maasen, S., Mendelsohn, E., Weingart, P. (eds) Biology as Society, Society as Biology: Metaphors. Sociology of the Sciences, vol 18. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-011-0673-3_11

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-011-0673-3_11

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-1-4020-0251-9

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-011-0673-3

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics