Skip to main content

Geometry: the Model of Knowledge

  • Chapter
Philosophy and Geometry

Part of the book series: The Western Ontario Series in Philosophy of Science ((WONS,volume 66))

  • 232 Accesses

Abstract

We have to analyze in this chapter what is the role of Euclidean geometry in the Critique of Pure Reason. Oversimplifying things for the sake of clarity, we can, first of all describe the dynamic nature that exists between the three faculties of knowledge — sensibility, imagination, understanding.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. For the complex differences on the treatment of the faculty of imagination in the two Kantian deductions cf. for example Cassirer, 1907, vol. II, and 1918; Heidegger, 1929; Palumbo, 1985; Scaravelli 1973; Wolff, 1943.

    Google Scholar 

  2. From this passage some authors have drawn their interpretation of imagination as a sort of unconscious understanding.

    Google Scholar 

  3. We overlook the problem of time.

    Google Scholar 

  4. On the construction of a concept as regarding the constitution of a single object (and therefore on the “singular” character of intuition), see the considerations of chapter 3, section 2, this book.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Examples from the area of computational medical knowledge-based systems (able to simulate diagnostic reasoning), machine discovery (able to simulate scientific discovery), visual and analogical reasoning, etc. are given for instance in Magnani, 1988, 1999a and b, in my recent book Magnani, 2001, and in Magnani, Nersessian, and Thagard, 1999.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Like the slave boy of Plato’s Meno dialogue, that is in front of an analogous inferential problem. The story of Socrates that teaches geometry to the slave is illustrated in chapter 6, section 1.

    Google Scholar 

  7. It is well-known that by axiomatizing Euclidean geometry in a rigorous modern way theorems can be deduced through logical reasoning without resorting to real or imagined figures, beginning with a relatively small number of primitive propositions and using inference rules. The problems implicated by this possibility, which seem to attenuate the importance of “constructions”, are treated in chapter 3, sections 1 and 2. On recent logical models of “diagrammatic” geometrical reasoning see chapter 7, section 6.2.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Cf. on these topics and the differences between the First and Second deduction, Palumbo, 1985, pp. 35–50, and Broad, 1988, pp. 180–224.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Notwithstanding its tendency to a kind of psychologism of the innate dispositions of human beings.

    Google Scholar 

  10. And I would add, by “creative abduction”, cf. above.

    Google Scholar 

  11. On the role of frame-like descriptions of concepts in scientific conceptual change cf. Magnani, 1999a and b.

    Google Scholar 

  12. At least this is the interpretation imposed by his followers that sustain the central role of the linguistic “dimension”, of course the problem in Wittgenstein is much more subtle and complex, cf., for example, Bouveresse, 1987.

    Google Scholar 

  13. On the importance of the transcendental tradition in emphasizing the specific role of mathematics in scientific knowledge see below chapter 3, section 6.

    Google Scholar 

  14. It is Euclid’s Proposition XXXII, Book I, cf. Figure 1.

    Google Scholar 

  15. “Constructing by clicking” is the recent Java version of this ancient problem of geometrical construction. Cf. the web site http://sunsite.ubc.ca/DigitalMathArchive/Euclid/java/html/pythagoras.html, devoted to illustrating many proofs of Pythagoras’ theorem, where the user can “construct” geometrical demonstrations by clicking on the figures presented, moving points and features of geometrical diagrams. (Cf. also footnotes 26 and 27, chapter 7, this book).

    Google Scholar 

  16. I would say, not just a mere definition, that does not “pass beyond” the concept. 17 This is a precise rule.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Cf. chapter 3, sections 1 and 2, this book.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Cf. also on this topic Palumbo, 1985, pp. 62–68, Parsons, 1969, and Winterburne, 1988.

    Google Scholar 

  19. This passage was corrected by Vaihinger and it is accepted by the majority of interpreters.

    Google Scholar 

  20. The original passage is: “The roundness which is thought in the former can be intuited in the latter”. Isaac (1968) considers the original version to be more acceptable since, in the geometrical concept, the roundness is intuited, because constructed in intuition. On the contrary, he states that in the plate the roundness is thought, because this object cannot be constructed. Both interpretations seem plausible.

    Google Scholar 

  21. In chapter 6 we will see that this kind of reasoning can be usefully illustrated by means of the concept of “selective abduction”.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Cf. also chapter 3, section 5, this book.

    Google Scholar 

  23. The history of non-Euclidean geometries and related philosophical and epistemological problems, as a background to better understand many of the argumentation’s of this book, are provided in Magnani, 1978. The following is a list of texts related to the history of non-Euclidean geometry and philosophy of geometry and space. Fundamental books, treatises, and bibliographies: Barbarin, 1902; Bonola, 1899–1900–1902 (bibliography), 1906, 1925; Enriques, 1918 and 1923–1927; Fano, 1898 and 1935; Halsted, 1878–1879 (bibliography); Sommerville, 1911 (bibliography) and 1914; Stäckel and Engel, 1895–1913. More recent books and articles: Boi, 1991; Capec, 1–976 (including many historical texts from the origins of geometry up to now); Coxeter, 1945; Gray, 1979; Greenberg, 1980; Guéridon and Dieudonné, 1978; Kline, 1972 (chapters 34, 37–39); Kulczycki, 1961; Lanczos, 1970; Magnani, 1975, 1977a (on Lobachevsky); Moise, 1963; Rosenfeld, 1988; Toth, 1972 and 1991 (on the cultural and scientific controversies related to the non-Euclidean geometries); Van Fraassen, 1985 (on the related problem of the philosophy of space); Weyl, 1967 (chapters 3–4).

    Google Scholar 

  24. Cf. also the considerations given in the subsection 5.3.1 of chapter 3, this book.

    Google Scholar 

  25. On this old-fashioned aspects of Kantian philosophy see chapter 3, section 6.

    Google Scholar 

  26. On the interesting question of the so-called “mathematical schematism”, and the related Petitot’s interpretation of Kantian thought about space and mathematics, see chapter 3, section 7, this book.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2001 Kluwer Academic Publishers

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Magnani, L. (2001). Geometry: the Model of Knowledge. In: Philosophy and Geometry. The Western Ontario Series in Philosophy of Science, vol 66. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-010-9622-5_2

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-010-9622-5_2

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-1-4020-0241-0

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-010-9622-5

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics