Skip to main content

Toward a Unified Theory of Game, Play, and Social Action

  • Chapter
The Structure of Social Inconsistencies

Abstract

Sociological theory has to deal with processes of type formation within frames of social relevance. Modes of interaction like games, plays, and projected social actions have to be differentiated on the background of a theory of social types. Most discriminative for such an endeavor are differences in the temporal dimensions and in the relevance structures of interactional situations.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. The question (see sect. 4.42) of what determines the chance for an arisal of social inconsistencies has thus been answered for an important instance. The prevalence of playing-at-a-theme, of play and also of game, especially in the “play-world of the child,” is a consequence of the incipient state of the child’s typificatory scheme of “body.”

    Google Scholar 

  2. Marilyn Monroe’s attempts to free herself from the limits set by the symbolic type of “sexbomb” show the tragic consequences and the personally uncontrollable inertia of these inconsistencies. —It need not be stressed again that these phenomena are entirely different from the well-known problem in role-theory that reciprocal role typifications also have a certain inertia.

    Google Scholar 

  3. The studies of Plessner and of Merleau-Ponty are among the most important in this field. See: Helmuth Plessner, Die Stufen des Organischen und der Mensch (Berlin, DeGruyter, 1928 ), and Maurice Merleau-Ponty, Phenomenology of Perception ( London, Routledge-Kegan Paul, 1962 ).

    Google Scholar 

  4. G. H. Mead, Present, p. 186.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Compare sect. 1.3.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Quoted by Plessner in Lachen und Weinen, p. 102.

    Google Scholar 

  7. This is a hypothesis. The subsequent analysis will explore and test ist implications.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Some excellent illustrations may be found, for instance, in Eric Berne’s Games People Play. What he describes as “Sexual Games” (pp. 123–131) are “strategically” structured patterns of interaction: hence they are also “games” in the above sense. Their pattern is composed of limits set by enactment of the common symbolic type of “making love.” These limits are social and can hardly be explained by “sexual instincts” as Berne suggests. The interactional mode of “making-love-to-each-other” is, of course, play.

    Google Scholar 

  9. See sect. 5.23: The “more stringent definition of social temporality” stipulates that the passage of interaction has to be structured by the incipient event, resp. by the symbolic type.

    Google Scholar 

  10. This “imposition of rationality” is a phenomenon not sufficiently clarified in sociological theory. It is related to the problem of intersubjectivity. I should like to state a conjecture: If Peirce’ and Durkheim’s claims that logic and rationality have a social basis are correct, then this basis could be clarified by studying further the intermediary phases between play and game. For Peirce see Coll. Pap., 2.654ff, 5.311, 5.354–357, 5.378, 5.384. For Durkheim see especially his The Elementary Forms of the Religious Life (London, Allan, 1954) esp. p. 418.

    Google Scholar 

  11. See sect. 5.11.

    Google Scholar 

  12. See sect. 5.13.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Sect. 7.1.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Relevance maintained by symbolic types and relevance maintained by typificatory schemes in role interaction must be distinguished. If I talk about “degeneration of social roles into symbolic types” I do not connect any value judgement with the term “degeneration.” I suggest, however, that role interaction has been overestimated in recent sociological theory and that the consequences of the enactment of symbolic types for personal identity and for the perception of social values are considerable.

    Google Scholar 

  15. See sect. 6.24.

    Google Scholar 

  16. If any of these three characteristics is missing, no playing of a game takes place. In this case, the interactional mode of game prevails as such. A systematic study of games would have to introduce further distinctions here. For instance, Goffman distinguishes game, as a “body of rules,” and play as a “particular instance of a given game played from beginning to end.” Playing is the “process of move-taking,” whereas the “varieties of interaction that occur among persons who are face to face” in order to play a game is called gaming. (E. Goffman, Encounters, pp. 35f.) — My terminology, obviously, is different from Goffman’s.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Mathematical game analysis similarly speaks of goals as “imputations.” Compare Neumann-Morgenstern, Theory of Games, pp. 34–37.

    Google Scholar 

  18. See sect. 8.2 for the “tough guy” constituted in playing football.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Compare Goffman’s essay “Fun in Games” in: Encounters, pp. 17–81.

    Google Scholar 

  20. See sect. 5.11.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Compare the similar formulation of Schütz for the span of the project. See Social World, p. 62.

    Google Scholar 

  22. See sect. 1.3.

    Google Scholar 

  23. See sect. 5.14.

    Google Scholar 

  24. A. Gehlen, Mensch, p. 224. — Gehlen quotes immediately following George H. Mead’s notion of “generalized other.” It is hard to see how this Meadian notion can support a teleological concept like Gehlen’s “Zucht.” See sect. 6. 12.

    Google Scholar 

  25. See sect. 5.4.

    Google Scholar 

  26. Sartre, Search, pp. 128f.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Durkheim described this state of affairs as “economic anomie.” See esp. his foreword to the 2nd ed. of Division of Labor.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Compare sect. 5.4.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1970 Martinus Nijhoff, The Hague, Netherlands

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Grathoff, R.H. (1970). Toward a Unified Theory of Game, Play, and Social Action. In: The Structure of Social Inconsistencies. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-010-3215-5_7

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-010-3215-5_7

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-247-5006-1

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-010-3215-5

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics