Advertisement

Negative Aspects of Bergson’s Epistemology — Its Relations to Bachelard, Bridgman and Empirio-Criticism

  • Milič Čapek
Part of the Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science book series (BSPS, volume 7)

Abstract

The negative aspect of Bergson’s epistemological method consists in a difficult and perpetually renewed effort to break certain intellectual habits, that is, certain associations of ideas which, by the effect of familiarity and repetition, appear solid and unbreakable. They appear so solid that the rationalists endowed them with the status of a priori principles constituting the immutable or, as Kant called it, “transcendental” structure of the human mind which no future experience can ever challenge. In truth this alleged transcendental structure is nothing but what Gaston Bachelard called “geometrical subconscious” or, in the terms strongly reminiscent of Bergson’s language, “the Euclidian infrastructure which is formed in a mind subject to experience of solid bodies both natural and manufactured”.1 It is extremely difficult to keep in check our Euclidian kinetic-corpuscular subconscious which is the depositary of our daily individual, as well as ancestral, experience. This is why, as the late Professor Bridgman observed not without humour, longing for mechanical explanation has “all the tenacity of original sin” and “just as the old monks struggled to subdue the flesh, so must the physicist struggle to subdue this sometimes nearly irresistible, but perfectly unjustifiable desire”.2

Keywords

Human Mind Modern Physic Biological Theory Late Professor Intellectual Effort 
These keywords were added by machine and not by the authors. This process is experimental and the keywords may be updated as the learning algorithm improves.

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. 1.
    G. Bachelard, Le nouvel esprit scientifique, Paris 1946, p. 37.Google Scholar
  2. 2.
    P. W. Bridgman, The Logic of Modern Physics, Macmillan, New York, 1927, p. 47.Google Scholar
  3. 3.
    G. Bachelard, La philosophic du non. Essai d’une philosophic du nouvel esprit scientifique, Paris 1949.Google Scholar
  4. 4.
    A. Thibaudet, Le bergsonisme, I, pp. 165–169. (Chapter ‘Les dissociations des idees’.)Google Scholar
  5. 5.
    Richard Avenarius, Philosophic als Denken der Welt gemass dem Princip des kleinsten Kraftmasses, 3rd Ed., Berlin 1917.Google Scholar
  6. 6.
    Theodule Ribot, L’evolution des idees gene rales, 4th Ed., Paris 1915, p. 149Google Scholar
  7. 7.
    Vladimir Jankelevitch, ‘La signification spirituelle du principe d’economie’, Revue philosophique 53e annee, 105, 88–126, in particular p. 92. This essay was later in–corporated in his book L’alternative, Paris 1938, Chapter II.Google Scholar
  8. 8.
    Willard Van Orman Quine, From a Logical Point of View, Harper Torchbook, 1961, p. 44.Google Scholar
  9. 9.
    Gustave Juvet, La structure des nouvelles theories physiques, Paris, 1933, p. 135.Google Scholar
  10. 10.
    N. Berdyaev, The Nature of the Free Act (transl. by D. C. Lowrie ), Harper, 1954, p. 40.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© D. Reidel Publishing Company, Dordrecht, Holland 1971

Authors and Affiliations

  • Milič Čapek

There are no affiliations available

Personalised recommendations